2010
DOI: 10.1007/s11750-010-0157-5
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

1-concave basis for TU games and the library game

Abstract: The study of 1-convex/1-concave TU games possessing a nonempty core and for which the nucleolus is linear was initiated by Driessen and Tijs (Methods Oper. Res. 46:395-406, 1983) and Driessen (OR Spectrum 7:19-26, 1985). However, until recently appealing abstract and practical examples of these classes of games were missing. The paper solves these drawbacks. We introduce a 1-concave basis for the entire space of all TU games wherefrom it follows that every TU game is either 1-convex/1-concave or is a sum of … Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
2
1

Citation Types

0
14
0

Year Published

2011
2011
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
6
1

Relationship

1
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 10 publications
(14 citation statements)
references
References 8 publications
0
14
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Finally, an alternative proof of the main Theorem 3 is treated in [11] in terms of Dutch soccer teams and their potential fans. Three other applications of oneconcavity or one-convexity, called library game, coinsurance game, and the dual game of the Stackelberg oligopoly game, respectively, can be found in [10,12,13]. The nucleolus for 2convex games is treated in [14].…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…Finally, an alternative proof of the main Theorem 3 is treated in [11] in terms of Dutch soccer teams and their potential fans. Three other applications of oneconcavity or one-convexity, called library game, coinsurance game, and the dual game of the Stackelberg oligopoly game, respectively, can be found in [10,12,13]. The nucleolus for 2convex games is treated in [14].…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Corollary 10. As shown in [10], the well-known Shapley cost allocation charged to the agents of any -person complementary unanimity cost game ⟨ , ⟩ amounts Sh ( , ) = 1 ∀ ∈ \ , = 0, every -person airport cost game with stand-alone costs ({ }), ∈ , ordered as an increasing sequence, is associated with a bicycle cost game with adapted stand-alone costs ({ }) − ({ }), ∈ , to be ordered as an increasing sequence. In this setting, (21) is a direct consequence of (20) applied to this latter bicycle cost game.…”
Section: Corollarymentioning
confidence: 91%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…The first practical example of a 1-concave game, the so-called library cost game, and the 1-concave complementary unanimity basis for the entire space of TU games were introduced in Driessen et al (2010). A co-insurance game under the hypothesis of Theorem 1 provides a new practical example of a 1-convex game.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Note that U T (N ) = 0 for all T N , except T = ∅. As is shown in [10], the well known Shapley value cost allocation charged to the players of any n-person complementary unanimity cost game (N, U T ) agrees with the semi-egalitarian rule such that members of T receive less the unitary amount, that is,…”
Section: The Shapley Value Of the Sharing Car Pooling Cost Game And Tmentioning
confidence: 61%