DOI: 10.1108/s0092-4563(2012)0000038011
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

9. The Manner/Result Complementarity Revisited: A Syntactic Approach

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
20
0

Publication Types

Select...
6
1

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 60 publications
(20 citation statements)
references
References 13 publications
0
20
0
Order By: Relevance
“…If complex meanings do not derive from lexical semantic components but are read off the (sub-)event syntactic structure, then semantics must provide systematic means of composing complex events out of simple ones. This idea is at the basis of much recent work in argument structure (Basilico 2012;Borer 2005;H&K 1993Harley 2008;Marantz 2005;Mateu & Acedo-Matell an 2012;Pylkk€ anen 2008;Ramchand 2008;Sch€ afer 2008;among others). If my analyses of direct lexical causatives without CAUSE and lexical inchoatives without BECOME are correct, they argue that a semantic rule that composes a dynamic event and a state has a general application and is, after all, needed and desirable.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 98%
“…If complex meanings do not derive from lexical semantic components but are read off the (sub-)event syntactic structure, then semantics must provide systematic means of composing complex events out of simple ones. This idea is at the basis of much recent work in argument structure (Basilico 2012;Borer 2005;H&K 1993Harley 2008;Marantz 2005;Mateu & Acedo-Matell an 2012;Pylkk€ anen 2008;Ramchand 2008;Sch€ afer 2008;among others). If my analyses of direct lexical causatives without CAUSE and lexical inchoatives without BECOME are correct, they argue that a semantic rule that composes a dynamic event and a state has a general application and is, after all, needed and desirable.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 98%
“…However, we have seen that this is not feasible: the movement of the legs does not have to cause the movement of the person, and the movement of the person does not have to cause the movement of the legs, as example (17), repeated here as (32), demonstrates. Another option is to say that the movement of the hand is the only verbal head ('to move'), and that the movement of the fingers is a Manner root ('by moving one's legs') that attaches to the main verb, similar to what is suggested for some manner verbs in English (Mateu and Acedo-Matellán 2012;Acedo-Matellán and Mateu 2015). Note that in (33), there is only one proc head (MOVE), to which a manner root MOVE2 is adjoined.…”
Section: (31)mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…However, it has been shown that these verbs in spoken languages do not in fact involve two separate event structures. Argument structure is determined by the motion event structure, and the sound emission verbal root is adjoined to the motion verbal head as manner (Mateu and Acedo-Matellán 2012;Acedo-Matellán and Mateu 2015). Above we have argued that such an analysis cannot account for the RSL data.…”
Section: (42)mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Research has extensively shown that exposure to a syntactic structure influences to different degrees the way we subsequently process a similar structure in comprehension and production in what has been called syntactic priming, structural priming, or structural persistence (e.g., Bock, 1986 ; Bock and Loebell, 1990 ; Bock et al, 1992 , 2007 ; Branigan et al, 1995 , 2000 ; Pickering and Branigan, 1998 , 1999 ; Hare and Goldberg, 1999 ; Pickering et al, 2002 , 2013 ; Loebell and Bock, 2003 ; Ferreira and Bock, 2006 ; Thothathiri and Snedeker, 2006 , 2008a , b ; Carminati et al, 2008 ; Hartsuiker et al, 2008 ; Pickering and Ferreira, 2008 ; Tooley et al, 2009 ; Tooley and Traxler, 2010 ; Segaert et al, 2012 , 2013 ; Tooley and Bock, 2014 ; Traxler et al, 2014 ; Wittenberg et al, 2014 ). The main goal of this paper is to use the process of syntactic priming as a behavioral tool to test two competing theoretical approaches to argument structure, namely (i) Hale and Keyser's ( 1993 ; 1998 ; 2002 ) approach as recently developed in Mateu ( 2002 ), Acedo-Matellán ( 2010 ), Mateu and Acedo-Matellán ( 2012 ), and Acedo-Matellán and Mateu ( 2013 ), what we will refer to as the generative semantics approach to argument structure, and (ii) Marantz ( 2005 ; 2011 ; 2013 ), which we will call interpretive semantics approach. These two theoretical models illustrate two different views of the syntax-semantics mapping.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…As pointed out in Marantz ( 2005 ) (see also Poeppel and Embick, 2005 ), generative grammar can and should serve as a source of theoretical hypotheses about the representation of language in the mind and brain and how this is processed, to be formally assessed through standard experimental methods. In this paper we take two competing theories of argument structure, (i) Acedo-Matellán ( 2010 ); Mateu and Acedo-Matellán ( 2012 ), and Acedo-Matellán and Mateu ( 2013 ), and (ii) Marantz ( 2005 ; 2011 ; 2013 ) and test their claims and predictions with respect to the representation and processing of syntactic argument structure. Both theories are framed within Chomsky's Minimalist Program, and they both adopt a neoconstructionist view of syntax, whereby argument structure is not lexically projected 2 but created in the syntax by the computational system, a single generative engine for all structure building where minimal units of syntactico-semantic features are combined through the operation of merge to create hierarchical syntactic structures that will then receive a semantic and phonological interpretation.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%