1987
DOI: 10.2307/1913561
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

A Refinement of Sequential Equilibrium

Abstract: JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.We propose a refinement of sequential equilibrium for extensive form games by generalizing a restriction proposed for signaling games in Cho and Kreps (1987).2 The restriction i… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
46
0
1

Year Published

1992
1992
2013
2013

Publication Types

Select...
6
3

Relationship

1
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 80 publications
(47 citation statements)
references
References 10 publications
0
46
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…On the other hand the low-valuation buyer's equilibrium payoff is zero in example P1, whereas rejection of p 1 would yield an expected payoff of (1-L ) if the seller believed that rejection signaled the low valuation. Forward induction then implies that the seller should indeed interpret an unexpected rejection as a signal that the buyer's valuation was low, since the low-valuation buyer might gain by rejection, while the high-valuation Cho (1987) defines forward induction equilibrium as a refinement of sequential equilibrium in general (finite) games; this generalizes the Cho-Kreps (1987) Intuitive Criterion, which is formally defined only for signaling games. The consistency condition is strengthened to include "introspective" consistency, meaning that after a deviation by an informed player, the belief system puts no weight on types of that player which would receive less than the equilibrium payoff, if everyone behaves optimally, unless all types would lose.…”
Section: Implications Of Forward Inductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…On the other hand the low-valuation buyer's equilibrium payoff is zero in example P1, whereas rejection of p 1 would yield an expected payoff of (1-L ) if the seller believed that rejection signaled the low valuation. Forward induction then implies that the seller should indeed interpret an unexpected rejection as a signal that the buyer's valuation was low, since the low-valuation buyer might gain by rejection, while the high-valuation Cho (1987) defines forward induction equilibrium as a refinement of sequential equilibrium in general (finite) games; this generalizes the Cho-Kreps (1987) Intuitive Criterion, which is formally defined only for signaling games. The consistency condition is strengthened to include "introspective" consistency, meaning that after a deviation by an informed player, the belief system puts no weight on types of that player which would receive less than the equilibrium payoff, if everyone behaves optimally, unless all types would lose.…”
Section: Implications Of Forward Inductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…13 buyer necessarily loses. This means that the equilibrium in example P1 is not a forward-induction equilibrium, in the sense of Cho (1987). 10 The same argument rules out all pooling equilibria with…”
mentioning
confidence: 96%
“…Nonetheless, (µ2) and (π2) do satisfy the spirit of the Cho-Kreps intuitive criterion, since beliefs are revised (as they must be) following a credible signal of strength. (The qualifier "in the spirit of " is used here, since the refinements by Cho and Kreps (1987) and Cho (1987) are not formally defined for models with two-sided signalling and a continuum of actions.) In addition, the beliefs (µ2) have a desirable property: if a trader mistakenly reveals that she is weaker than she truly is by making an offer too early, it is the trader's best response to correct the mistake by delaying her next offer so as to reveal the truth.…”
Section: B -P(s B) = δ(B -P(b S)) and P(b S) -S = δ( P(s B) -S)mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…When we consider the jurors'ex-ante problem of searching (`; m) in the joint type space, the search exhibits diminishing marginal returns. Both the probability of terminating the conversation 3 and the expected value of the true information is decreasing in the number of rounds. As the bene…t of investment into information aggregation is realized only when the information is utilized and the verdict is taken, the total return on investment ex-post is actually the marginal return to the investment ex-ante.…”
Section: Proposition 2 In Any Equilibrium (L; M ) Conversations Get mentioning
confidence: 98%