2015
DOI: 10.1093/logcom/exv043
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

A Van Benthem/Rosen theorem for coalgebraic predicate logic

Abstract: Coalgebraic modal logic serves as a unifying framework to study a wide range of modal logics beyond the relational realm, including probabilistic and graded logics as well as conditional logics and logics based on neighbourhoods and games. Coalgebraic predicate logic (CPL), a generalization of a neighbourhoodbased first-order logic introduced by Chang, has been identified as a natural first-order extension of coalgebraic modal logic, which in particular coincides with the standard first-order correspondence la… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
4
1

Citation Types

2
16
0

Year Published

2017
2017
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
3
1
1

Relationship

3
2

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 9 publications
(18 citation statements)
references
References 43 publications
2
16
0
Order By: Relevance
“…The need for assuming that the set Λ of modalities is finite is specific to quantitative Hennessy-Milner theorems (and implicitly present also in the existing [0, 1]-valued version of the theorem [37]), and not needed in the two-valued case [45,50]. It relates to the total boundedness claim in Theorem 6.1, and features also in the van Benthem theorem, where in fact it is needed also in the two-valued case [52]; indeed, proofs of the original van Benthem theorem start by assuming, in that case w.l.o.g., that there are only finitely many propositional atoms and relational modalities. In our running examples, only the ones featuring metric transition systems are affected by this assumption; indeed, for our theorems to apply to such systems, the space of labels needs to be finite.…”
Section: Modal Approximationmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…The need for assuming that the set Λ of modalities is finite is specific to quantitative Hennessy-Milner theorems (and implicitly present also in the existing [0, 1]-valued version of the theorem [37]), and not needed in the two-valued case [45,50]. It relates to the total boundedness claim in Theorem 6.1, and features also in the van Benthem theorem, where in fact it is needed also in the two-valued case [52]; indeed, proofs of the original van Benthem theorem start by assuming, in that case w.l.o.g., that there are only finitely many propositional atoms and relational modalities. In our running examples, only the ones featuring metric transition systems are affected by this assumption; indeed, for our theorems to apply to such systems, the space of labels needs to be finite.…”
Section: Modal Approximationmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In the two-valued setting, there has been increased recent interest in variants and generalizations of this result (e.g. [54,14,52,22,55,1])…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…Bisimulations have been studied for the guarded fragment and many variations [33], [38], [46]. Bisimulations have also been studied recently for coalgebraic modal logics [47], [48] and fuzzy modal logics [49].…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Sahlqvist theory is currently a very active field of research. This field has significantly broadened its scope in recent years, extending the state of the art and the benefits of Sahlqvist theory from modal logic to a class of logics which includes, among others, intuitionistic and lattice-based (modal) logics [32,20], substructural logics [44,59,21], non-normal modal logics [28,51], hybrid logics [24], many-valued logics [45], mu-calculus [71,10,8,2,9], and coalgebraic logic [46,57]. The common ground to these results is the recognition that algebraic and order-theoretic notions play a fundamental role in the various incarnations of the Sahlqvist phenomenon.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%