In discussions of whether and how pragmatic considerations can make a difference to what one ought to believe, two sets of cases feature. The first set, which dominates the debate about pragmatic reasons for belief, is exemplified by cases of being financially bribed to believe (or withhold from believing) something. The second set, which | 533 WORSNIP 2 | PRAGMATIC ENCROACHMENT, AND REASONS VS.
THRESHOLD PRAGMATISMAs I mentioned, moderate pragmatism tends to be the favored view of advocates of the "pragmatic encroachment" thesis. According to this thesis, pragmatic considerations make a difference to what one ought to believe tout court via making a difference to what one epistemically ought to believe, or is justified in believing. 5 As a matter of logic, there's nothing inconsistent about combining pragmatic encroachment with what I'm calling hard pragmatism. But pragmatic encroachers face strong pressure to be moderate pragmatists. For it seems wild to suggest that in a case like Bribe, my offer of money to you to withhold belief makes a difference to what you're epistemically justified in believing. Thus, pragmatic encroachers incur the explanatory burden of explaining how to keep their pragmatism moderate. 6 It may seem initially puzzling how pragmatic considerations could make a difference to what one epistemically ought to believe, as pragmatic encroachers hold. If pragmatic considerations are reasons for or against belief, the character of those reasons does not seem to be epistemic in any good sense. A natural and popular answer to this challenge is to hold that pragmatic considerations do not make a difference to what one ought to believe by constituting reasons for or against belief at all (as they would on a view that we can reasons pragmatism), but rather by serving as what we might call "threshold-shifting considerations" (let's call this latter view threshold pragmatism). In particular, pragmatic considerations determine how much evidence is required for (epistemically) justified belief. 7 They thus play a different role to evidential considerations, which serve as reasons. I like to think of this using an illustration that I'll call the "beaker of reasons":5 My formulation of pragmatic encroachment makes it a view about justified belief, whereas many of its advocates (especially its early advocates) make it a view about knowledge (Hawthorne, 2004; Stanley, 2005). I find the view about justified belief more instructive for my purposes here, where I want to compare moderate pragmatism with hard pragmatism, where neither of those views are about knowledge. Most advocates of pragmatic encroachment on knowledge also embrace pragmatic encroachment on justified belief (see, e.g., Fantl & McGrath, 2002, 2009 Schroeder, 2012a: 268). Moss (2018) constitutes an exception to this, at least when it comes to credences. 6 One can imagine a view that accepts pragmatic encroachment in cases like Risks, as well as accepting pragmatism (but not pragmatic encroachment) in cases like Bribe. This would square pra...