1977
DOI: 10.1007/bf00262046
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Classical second-order intensional logic with maximal propositions

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
5
0

Year Published

1978
1978
1980
1980

Publication Types

Select...
4

Relationship

2
2

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 4 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 6 publications
0
5
0
Order By: Relevance
“…[6] For further discussion of this point, see [10], section O. For issues related to ontological commitment to modalities and expression of this commitment by bindable modal variables, see [7], paragraph 2.…”
Section: We Refer [2]mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…[6] For further discussion of this point, see [10], section O. For issues related to ontological commitment to modalities and expression of this commitment by bindable modal variables, see [7], paragraph 2.…”
Section: We Refer [2]mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Our aim in this paper is to point out that within a system with maximal propositions which was developed in [3], a notion of truth and of coherence may be defined. We shall prove a theorem to show that our notion of truth may plausibly be called a coherence notion of truth.…”
Section: Maximal Propositions and The Coherence Theory Of Truth I I Nmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The unary truth operator to be defined below is likewise similar to the binary operator Tap in [12], p. 90. 3 We are aware that given CMFC2, some philosophers might object to saying that = expresses genuine prepositional identity. This is because in CMFC2, (A = B) amounts to ((A <-> B) = T) and if h(A <-> B), h(A = B).…”
Section: University Of Victoriamentioning
confidence: 99%
See 2 more Smart Citations