2001
DOI: 10.1080/002017401750261563
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Concepts and Intuitions: Adorno After the Linguistic Turn

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
4
0
1

Year Published

2002
2002
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
4
3
1

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 24 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
0
4
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…A true reconciliation of subject and object, reason and nature, 'does not annex the alien with philosophical imperialism; rather it would have its happiness in this: that the alien stays, in its permitted nearness, the distant and the different, beyond its heterogeneity and beyond its own ' (1973: 191). I concur with Finke (2001) in characterizing Adorno as calling for an 'enlarged space of reasons' (ibid. : 175), insofar as cognitive authority extends beyond conceptual norms to the sensuous particulars themselves.…”
Section: 'The Cognitive Utopia': Adorno's Quartum Quidmentioning
confidence: 75%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…A true reconciliation of subject and object, reason and nature, 'does not annex the alien with philosophical imperialism; rather it would have its happiness in this: that the alien stays, in its permitted nearness, the distant and the different, beyond its heterogeneity and beyond its own ' (1973: 191). I concur with Finke (2001) in characterizing Adorno as calling for an 'enlarged space of reasons' (ibid. : 175), insofar as cognitive authority extends beyond conceptual norms to the sensuous particulars themselves.…”
Section: 'The Cognitive Utopia': Adorno's Quartum Quidmentioning
confidence: 75%
“…22. Finke (2001) thinks that both Adorno and McDowell hold that 'the point is to extend the conception of the space of reasons to incorporate an extra-conceptual dimension, constituting the normative framework for the experience of objects in the ''weighty sense''' (ibid. : 175; original emphasis) and that 'one must acknowledge not only non-inferential constraints upon thought but also that such constraints can be integrated with the space of reasons' (ibid.…”
Section: Notesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…3 There arises here a rather large question as to whether Adorno hereby runs afoul of the critique of the scheme/content distinction made by Quine, Davidson, et al This issue is fleshed out in Finke (2001); see also Hammer (2000). 4 Admittedly, this is not always clear: see Freud (1955, pp.…”
Section: Todd Hedrickmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Yet, "how can critical theory justify itself; how does it ground its own normative standpoint" (Pleasants, 1999: 155)? If they are serious about their endeavor, critical theorists must seek to identify the normative foundations of their own undertaking (see Finke, 2001 andHeld, 1980). Discursively motivated actors may wish to defend seemingly universal values (such as "liberty," "equality," or "fraternity"), particular forms of governance (such as direct or representational democracy), or specific sets of rights (such as civil, political, social, cultural, sexual, or human rights).…”
Section: Habermas's Epistemologymentioning
confidence: 99%