2017
DOI: 10.1007/s11023-017-9425-6
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Conditionals, Counterfactuals, and Rational Reasoning: An Experimental Study on Basic Principles

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
3
1
1

Citation Types

3
28
0

Year Published

2018
2018
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
5
4

Relationship

3
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 29 publications
(31 citation statements)
references
References 58 publications
3
28
0
Order By: Relevance
“…There is experimental evidence that people judge the probability of a counterfactual, "If A were the case, then C would be the case", as the conditional probability, PpC|Aq [68,78,80]. Moreover, when presented with causal, e.g., "If a patient were to take certain drug, the symptoms would diminish", or non-causal task material, e.g., "If the card were to show a square, it would be black", people judge the negations of the antecedents to be irrelevant to the evaluation of the counterfactuals [78,80]. These negations state the actual facts, e.g., "The patient does not take the drug", or "The side does not show a square", respectively.…”
Section: Two-premise Centering With Logical Relations and Counterfactmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…There is experimental evidence that people judge the probability of a counterfactual, "If A were the case, then C would be the case", as the conditional probability, PpC|Aq [68,78,80]. Moreover, when presented with causal, e.g., "If a patient were to take certain drug, the symptoms would diminish", or non-causal task material, e.g., "If the card were to show a square, it would be black", people judge the negations of the antecedents to be irrelevant to the evaluation of the counterfactuals [78,80]. These negations state the actual facts, e.g., "The patient does not take the drug", or "The side does not show a square", respectively.…”
Section: Two-premise Centering With Logical Relations and Counterfactmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Influenced by the above points, psychologists of reasoning have tested the CPH in controlled experiments, and found that people tend to conform to it for a wide range of conditionals, from indicative conditionals ( [31,35,73]) and conditional bets ( [5]) to counterfactuals and causal conditionals ( [69,70,81,82]). In the opinion of some authors, the CPH may not hold for conditionals if A then C when the antecedent A does not raise the probability of the conditional's consequent C ( [26,88]), but the significance of this finding is open to dispute ( [69]), and the general support for the CPH has had a major impact in psychology ( [30,68]), formal epistemology ( [76]), and philosophical logic ( [75,78,79,80]).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…1 In particular, see the axiomatizations of Renyi (1955) and Popper (1959), and Dubins's extension of de Finetti (1975). A sample of authors endorsing full conditional probabilities includes representatives from philosophy (van Fraassen 1976;Levi 1980;McGee 1994;Hájek 2003;Sprenger and Hartmann 2017), statistics (Kadane, Schervish, and Seidenfeld 1999), economics and game theory (Blume, Brandenburger, and Dekel 1991b;Myerson 1991;Hammond 1994;Battigalli and Veronesi 1996;Kohlberg and Reny 1997), logic (Adams 1966;Coletti and Scozzafava 2002;Makinson 2011), psychology (Pfeifer and Tulkki 2017), and computer science (Kraus, Lehmann, and Magidor 1990;Cowell, Dawid, Lauritzen, and Spiegelhalter 1999;Gilio 2012).…”
Section: Conditional Probability As Primitive: Full Conditional Probabilitiesmentioning
confidence: 99%