2016
DOI: 10.3196/004433016818285953
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Der Begriff der Tugend und die Grenzen der Tugendethik

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2020
2020
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
2
1

Relationship

1
2

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 3 publications
(3 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this challenge. 3 For this distinction see also Crisp (1996), p. 5-8; Adams (2006), p. 6 f. and Halbig (2013), p. 11. respects just mentioned: What was indeed present in the first half of the 20th century were arguably ethics of virtue of different stripes, be they consequentialist like Moore's or deontological like Frankena's; what was lacking however were prominent examples of virtue ethics proper.…”
Section: Some Distinctions and Definitionsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this challenge. 3 For this distinction see also Crisp (1996), p. 5-8; Adams (2006), p. 6 f. and Halbig (2013), p. 11. respects just mentioned: What was indeed present in the first half of the 20th century were arguably ethics of virtue of different stripes, be they consequentialist like Moore's or deontological like Frankena's; what was lacking however were prominent examples of virtue ethics proper.…”
Section: Some Distinctions and Definitionsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…2 It is controversial if even this categorization is appropriate (see, for example, Crisp 2015 for an argument that virtue ethics should not be considered as a standalone theory, but rather as a form of deontology), and we have to be aware that considerations typical of one family of moral theories also figure into moral theories that seem to fit in another group. As Christoph Halbig's differentiation between virtue ethics, ethics of virtue, and theory of virtue (Halbig 2013) demonstrates, virtues, as one of the key ethical concepts, can be found in moral theories that belong to very different groups of moral theories. We differentiate between different groups of moral theories in which the several concepts have different weights; although we know that categorizations often involve simplifications and a sacrifice of precision, we can seek out basic assumptions that can be assigned to different groups of moral theories.…”
Section: Moral Metatheorymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Interestingly, this connection between the questions different moral theories were built to answer plays a fundamentally different role in the context of moral theories than in the context of other scientific theories: in physics, different questions succeeded each other and led to different answers, but the resultant theories replaced each other. Remarkably, the questions to which moral theories give answers do not turn out to be superseded in this way.18 For discussions of the possibilities and problems of virtue ethics seeAnscombe 1958; Crisp/Slote 1997; Borchers 2001;Halbig 2013;Crisp 2015. Due to the aims of this paper, this is not the place to discuss virtues and their values, as it is similarly not the place to discuss the other aspects of moral theories which we are selecting for discussion.…”
mentioning
confidence: 98%