2016
DOI: 10.1086/688584
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Destructive Intergenerational Altruism

Abstract: Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen:Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden.Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen.Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
4
0

Year Published

2016
2016
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
4

Relationship

1
3

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 4 publications
(4 citation statements)
references
References 24 publications
0
4
0
Order By: Relevance
“…The intuition is that although dynasty i gives weight α C on the other dynasties, the other dynasties give weight α C /(N − 1) to dynasty i. This weight goes to zero as the number of dynasties goes to infinity (see also Asheim and Nesje, 2016).…”
Section: This Follows From Expression (12)mentioning
confidence: 97%
“…The intuition is that although dynasty i gives weight α C on the other dynasties, the other dynasties give weight α C /(N − 1) to dynasty i. This weight goes to zero as the number of dynasties goes to infinity (see also Asheim and Nesje, 2016).…”
Section: This Follows From Expression (12)mentioning
confidence: 97%
“…], the maximin (or leximin) criterion has then been adopted as yielding the most egalitarian among reasonable (that is, Paretian) social rankings." Asheim and Nesje (2016) use the maximin path as a benchmark for intergenerational equity, as the maximin welfare level offers a lower bound for welfare under other, more sophisticated criteria, such as the Calvo criterion, Sustainable Discounted Utility and Rank Discounted Utility, whose solutions may not be easy to compute in particular problems. Also, more sophisticated forms of intergenerational equity imply time-inconsistency, which has to be dealt with using sophisticated game-theoretic equilibrium selection (Asheim et al, 2020).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…examine the effect of population growth on optimal climate mitigation policies, comparing Total Utilitarianism (which is sensitive to the population size) and Average Utilitarianism (which is not) Anthoff and Emmerling (2019). disentangle the effect of intragenerational and intergenerational inequality aversions on the social cost of carbon.3 SeeAsheim and Ekeland (2016) for a discussion of the interest of this model to study sustainability issues, andAsheim and Nesje (2016) for the analysis of the optimal path in this model under various criteria of intergenerational equity. See alsoAsheim et al (2020) who discuss time-consistency issues for criteria that do not satisfy stationarity, and illustrate their results in theRamsey model.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation