2017
DOI: 10.1016/j.ijar.2017.02.006
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Graded cubes of opposition and possibility theory with fuzzy events

Abstract: The paper discusses graded extensions of the cube of opposition, a structure that naturally emerges from the square of opposition in philosophical logic. These extensions of the cube of opposition agree with possibility theory and its four set functions. This extended cube then provides a synthetic and unified view of possibility theory. This is an opportunity to revisit basic notions of possibility theory, in particular regarding the handling of fuzzy events. It turns out that in possibility theory, two exten… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
24
0

Year Published

2017
2017
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
6
1

Relationship

2
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 32 publications
(24 citation statements)
references
References 22 publications
0
24
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Within the latter field, Aristotelian diagrams have been used to study various logic-based approaches to knowledge representation, including fuzzy logic [16][17][18][19][20], modal-epistemic logic [21][22][23][24][25] and probabilistic logic [26][27][28]. Furthermore, Aristotelian diagrams are also used extensively to study (the connections between) other types of knowledge representation formalisms, such as formal argumentation theory [29][30][31][32], fuzzy set theory [33][34][35][36], formal concept analysis and possibility theory [37][38][39], rough set theory [37,40,41], multiple-criteria decision-making [42][43][44] and the theory of logical and analogical proportions [45][46][47][48][49]. In sum, then, Aristotelian diagrams have come to serve as visual tools that greatly facilitate communication, research and teaching in a wide variety of disciplines that deal with logical reasoning in all its facets.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…Within the latter field, Aristotelian diagrams have been used to study various logic-based approaches to knowledge representation, including fuzzy logic [16][17][18][19][20], modal-epistemic logic [21][22][23][24][25] and probabilistic logic [26][27][28]. Furthermore, Aristotelian diagrams are also used extensively to study (the connections between) other types of knowledge representation formalisms, such as formal argumentation theory [29][30][31][32], fuzzy set theory [33][34][35][36], formal concept analysis and possibility theory [37][38][39], rough set theory [37,40,41], multiple-criteria decision-making [42][43][44] and the theory of logical and analogical proportions [45][46][47][48][49]. In sum, then, Aristotelian diagrams have come to serve as visual tools that greatly facilitate communication, research and teaching in a wide variety of disciplines that deal with logical reasoning in all its facets.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In particular, the rhombic dodecahedron has been used in research on modal logic and dynamic epistemic logic [22,61], the tetrakis hexahedron and tetraicosahedron have been used to investigate modal logic [25,60,64,65], and the nested tetrahedron has been used to study (connections between) the knowledge representation formalisms of rough set theory, formal concept analysis and possibility theory [38,40]. (However, it should also be noted that our focus on B 4 precludes us from studying Aristotelian diagrams for knowledge representation formalisms that go beyond a Boolean setup, such as fuzzy logic and set theory [16][17][18][19][20][33][34][35][36]. The systematic (logical and diagrammatic) investigation of such non-classical Aristotelian diagrams is a matter of ongoing research.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…A gradual square of opposition can be defined by attaching variables α, ǫ, o, ι valued on a totally ordered set V to vertices A, E, O, I respectively, so as to respect the following constraints [12]:…”
Section: Gradual Square and Hexagonmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Proof. Based on results from Proposition 17 in [12], the two conditions π i = 1 for some i, and (1−a) → 0 ≤ 1−(a → 0) are sufficient to get…”
Section: Approximate Equality and Weighted Attributesmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation