1988
DOI: 10.1007/bf00132458
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

How vicious are cycles of intransitive choice?

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
25
0
3

Year Published

1990
1990
2017
2017

Publication Types

Select...
5
4

Relationship

0
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 65 publications
(28 citation statements)
references
References 16 publications
0
25
0
3
Order By: Relevance
“…Another heuristic that can lead to intransitivities is the majority rule (e.g., Kenneth O. May 1954;Maya Bar-Hillel and Avishai Margalit 1988). With this rule, the decisionmaker simply counts the number of dimensions where an option has an advantage (disregarding the magnitude of the advantages) and selects the option with the greatest number of advantages.…”
Section: When Are Violations Of Consistencymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Another heuristic that can lead to intransitivities is the majority rule (e.g., Kenneth O. May 1954;Maya Bar-Hillel and Avishai Margalit 1988). With this rule, the decisionmaker simply counts the number of dimensions where an option has an advantage (disregarding the magnitude of the advantages) and selects the option with the greatest number of advantages.…”
Section: When Are Violations Of Consistencymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Of course, it is questionable whether people maximize something at all [Selten, 1994], and whether they should do so from a normative point of view, as sometimes there might be good reasons for intransitive choices [Bar-Hillel and Margalit, 1988]. The latter means that substantive rationality can exist without formal rationality, tIowever, this paper will focus on the reverse case and assume formal rationality to be given, but not necessarily substantive rationality.…”
Section: Definition 1: the Choice-value Thesismentioning
confidence: 98%
“…And, there are numerous cases in which relative preferences are not decomposable into component attitudes at all. For example, intransitive relative preferences, violating unidimensionality, have been demonstrated repeatedly (e.g., Bar-Hillel & Margalit, 1988;Birnbaum, 1992;Shafir, Osherson, & Smith, 1990;Tversky, 1969) as have sub-or superadditivity (Anderson, 1977). Also, Hsee, Loewenstein, Blount, and Bazerman (1999) identified circumstances in which most participants preferred object A to object B when considered separately, while B was preferred to A in a relative comparison.…”
Section: Statementioning
confidence: 99%