Abstract:What methods can be used to understand the pain of others? Studying violence is very different than studying kinship or religion or other topics, which, however complex intellectually, are relatively risk free. In contrast, a study of violence is likely to put the observer at risk, both physically and psychologically. Violence also fragments experience, making it difficult to construct coherent or effective narratives about it. To overcome these difficulties, the texts under review variously combine 'experience-near' accounts with historical 'experience-distant' analysis. Each mode has its own advantages and disadvantages. Experience near reportage must rely on material that is fragmentary, oblique and restricted, but which is also emotionally intense and involving; experience distant analysis can achieve objectivity, systematic understanding, and intellectual Lindholm Violence 2 closure, but at the price of immediacy and expressive power. The most experience near material conveys trauma and depersonalization, the most experience distant accounts convey coherence and idealization; a mingling of the two extremes occurs at the middle range (violence, South Asia, social movements, ethnographic methodology).
Biographical Statement:CHARLES LINDHOLM, University Professor of Anthropology, Boston University.
REFLECTIONS ON VIOLENCE AND ETHNOGRAPHIC PRACTICEAs Adam Smith (1759) was the first to note, human beings blush with shame when they witness another's embarrassment, or smile when they observe another's happiness, but they are not able to experience someone else's pain. We may be grimace with disgust or horror when we witness agony or we may feel a secret sadistic thrill; we may extend a helping hand or we may be relieved (it wasn't me). But we don't actually feel the suffering of others, despite the cliché. Not even the slightest twinge.Yet, although we do not physically experience other's pain, in our culture we are endlessly fascinated by how the sufferer reacts. No accident occurs without its circle of spellbound onlookers, while graphic scenes of dismemberment entice and excite movie audiences. Since Schopenhauer (1819), philosophers have speculated that the morbid attraction to the misery of others arises from the human awareness of transience and the coincident imaginative capacity, which renders pain more frightening and also more mesmerizing for us than it is for animals. This is because pain disorganizes, fragments, and disintegrates identity. Since pain negates the coherent and autonomous self, there is a deep desire to observe how others respond when subjected to its shattering force. At the same time, in our personal lives pain is a catastrophe at worst, troublesome at best.Personal suffering is meaningless and disruptive. It should always be evaded, medicated, or otherwise alleviated.However, this attitude toward pain may not be as unanimous as it is often assumed to be. In many spiritual traditions, including Christianity, suffering is not viewed with fascinated horror when it occurs to othe...