2018
DOI: 10.31234/osf.io/ytqna
|View full text |Cite
Preprint
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Intuitive Expertise and Irrelevant Options

Abstract: In the so-called push dilemma, an out-of-control speed-train is about to run over five people and can only be stopped by pushing a heavy person onto the tracks. Most lay people and moral philosophers consider it morally wrong to kill the heavy person. Unger (1992, 1996), however, argued that adding irrelevant options to the push dilemma would overturn this intuition. In this paper, we empirically test Unger's claim with both lay people and expert moral philosophers. Including philosophical experts allowed us t… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
6
0

Year Published

2020
2020
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
5
1

Relationship

1
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 6 publications
(6 citation statements)
references
References 48 publications
0
6
0
Order By: Relevance
“…To illustrate this point consider a study that examines moral intuitions in different groups. Wiegmann, Horvath, and Meyer (under review) show that laypeople’s and philosopher’s moral intuitions around the trolley problem vary as a function of the number of available alternative options presented to them. Assuming that moral judgments are somehow special would in turn imply that these researchers would have to develop, from scratch, a theory of this based on unique preference reversal behavior specifically found in moral contexts.…”
Section: The Relationship Between Moral Psychology and Moral Philosophymentioning
confidence: 96%
“…To illustrate this point consider a study that examines moral intuitions in different groups. Wiegmann, Horvath, and Meyer (under review) show that laypeople’s and philosopher’s moral intuitions around the trolley problem vary as a function of the number of available alternative options presented to them. Assuming that moral judgments are somehow special would in turn imply that these researchers would have to develop, from scratch, a theory of this based on unique preference reversal behavior specifically found in moral contexts.…”
Section: The Relationship Between Moral Psychology and Moral Philosophymentioning
confidence: 96%
“…None of Swain et al's (2008) predictions concerning order effects with Truetemp cases could be consistently and robustly replicated in our three experiments, and it is thus at best unclear whether Truetemp intuitions are in fact unstable. So, if proponents of the negative program in experimental philosophy still want to use order effects to challenge the reliability of philosophical case judgments, they would be well advised to look elsewhere instead (e.g., Liao et al, 2012;Cushman, 2012, 2015;Machery et al, 2018;Wiegmann et al, 2012Wiegmann et al, , 2020. In any case, given the more robust empirical evidence that we presented in this paper, the metaphilosophical flurry created by Swain et al (2008) andWright's (2010) influential studies looks like mere alarmism in hindsight.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 83%
“…Third, we believe that the weight of the evidence suggests that Truetemp intuitions are in general not significantly influenced by their textual context, although we concede that Experiment 2 might indicate that they are influenced in a few situations. Of course, other manipulations of philosophical intuitions, including by order of presentation, might turn out to be more robust (e.g., the framing of the Gettier case in Machery et al, 2018; the order effects with moral cases in Wiegmann et al, 2012Wiegmann et al, , 2020, although recent work suggests that many philosophical intuitions are not much influenced, if at all, by slight manipulations (e.g., Cova et al, 2021;Kneer et al, 2021;Horvath & Wiegmann, 2022).…”
Section: No Philosophical P-hackingmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…The expertise defence (i.e., the claim that intuitions of professional philosophers about philosophical cases are not susceptible to irrelevant factors) has not been supported by experimental research (e.g., Feltz & Cokely, 2009; Horvath & Wiegmann, 2016, 2021; Schwitzgebel & Cushman, 2012; Wiegmann et al., 2020). However, there has been limited empirical research on the reliability of expert judgments outside the field of philosophy.…”
Section: Legal Expertisementioning
confidence: 99%