2015
DOI: 10.1017/s1358246115000296
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Is supererogation more than just costly sacrifice?

Abstract: I begin by examining the answer to a traditional puzzle concerning supererogatory acts: if they are good to do, why are they not required? The answer often given is that they are optional acts because they cost the agent too much. This view has parallels with the traditional view of religious sacrifice, which involves offering up something or someone valuable as a gift or victim and experiencing a ‘cost’ as part of the ritual. There are problems with the idea that costs justify the optional nature of supererog… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...

Citation Types

0
1
0

Year Published

2021
2021
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
2
1

Relationship

0
3

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 3 publications
(1 citation statement)
references
References 1 publication
0
1
0
Order By: Relevance
“…If helping my neighbor in this case is nonobligatory, it seems that it has to be supererogatory: something that it would be good and worthy to do, although it is not required. And indeed, philosophers discussing supererogation tend to regard favors in such terms (see, e.g., Benn, 2018, p. 333; Ferry, 2015, p. 52n5; Young, 2015, p. 127). In his book on supererogation, David Heyd lists doing favors as one of the “paradigmatic cases” of supererogation.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…If helping my neighbor in this case is nonobligatory, it seems that it has to be supererogatory: something that it would be good and worthy to do, although it is not required. And indeed, philosophers discussing supererogation tend to regard favors in such terms (see, e.g., Benn, 2018, p. 333; Ferry, 2015, p. 52n5; Young, 2015, p. 127). In his book on supererogation, David Heyd lists doing favors as one of the “paradigmatic cases” of supererogation.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%