2014
DOI: 10.1111/1467-9248.12129
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Is There a Distinctively Associative Account of Political Obligation?

Abstract: Associative theorists of political obligation argue that individuals are bound to the political society of which they are members and that membership itself is the primary ground of political obligation. Some critics claim that this argument fails in large part because any plausible associative account collapses into some non‐associative theory of political obligation. This article rejects such claims, arguing that associativism is in fact a distinctive approach to political obligation. Specifically, it holds … Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
5
0

Year Published

2016
2016
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
4
3
1

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 10 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 32 publications
0
5
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Although the actual consent theory became almost universally rejected (with some notable and partial exceptions like Beran 1987;Gilbert 2006;Simmons 1993), most contemporary accounts of PO still rely on some version of these background assumptions or at least subscribe to most of them. In other words, fair play theories (Dagger 1997;Rawls 1964), associative accounts (Dworkin 1986;Hardimon 1994;Horton 2006Horton , 2007Horton and Windeknecht 2015), natural duty theories (Rawls 1971;Wellmann 2005) etc. still largely follow the logic of the paradigmatic account of PO.…”
Section: The Received Viewmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Although the actual consent theory became almost universally rejected (with some notable and partial exceptions like Beran 1987;Gilbert 2006;Simmons 1993), most contemporary accounts of PO still rely on some version of these background assumptions or at least subscribe to most of them. In other words, fair play theories (Dagger 1997;Rawls 1964), associative accounts (Dworkin 1986;Hardimon 1994;Horton 2006Horton , 2007Horton and Windeknecht 2015), natural duty theories (Rawls 1971;Wellmann 2005) etc. still largely follow the logic of the paradigmatic account of PO.…”
Section: The Received Viewmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This picture directs our gaze not toward a foundational identity of the governed, constituted and characterized independently of the contingent political relations in which they find themselves, but toward their identity in political relations: membership, or lack thereof, in a political community. This picture stresses the ontological significance of identity: the existence of political relationships of a certain kind constitutes a reason for treating a regime as legitimate (Gilbert 2006;Renzo 2012;Horton and Windeknecht 2015).…”
Section: Three Picturesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Horton's argument, unlike Dworkin's, does not compromise the associative assumptions because, as Horton emphatically stresses, the community's being valuable from the universal point of view is only a necessary condition of membership counting as a reason, but not a sufficient one. “[I]t is not the moral conditions that a polity should meet […] that give rise to political obligations,” Horton argues, “rather, it is being a member of a particular polity” (Horton and Windeknecht, forthcoming). The two‐tier structure of his argument allows Horton to appeal to universal moral principles by way of accounting for the obligation‐generating character of relationships without thereby compromising the idea that it is the fact of relationship that is a basic reason for action.…”
Section: The Associative Argument and Its Criticsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…See also Horton and Windeknecht, forthcoming; Dworkin , 199; Tamir , 96–8. For critique, Wellman , 194–200 and , 221–2; Jeske , 38.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%