2017
DOI: 10.1080/17470218.2016.1276942
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Judgments of Moral Responsibility and Wrongness for Intentional and Accidental Harm and Purity Violations

Abstract: Two experiments examine whether people reason differently about intentional and accidental violations in the moral domains of harm and purity, by examining moral responsibility and wrongness judgments for violations that affect others or the self. The first experiment shows that intentional violations are judged to be worse than accidental ones, regardless of whether they are harm or purity violations-for example, Sam poisons his colleague versus Sam eats his dog, when participants judge how morally responsibl… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

4
17
0

Year Published

2018
2018
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
7

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 19 publications
(21 citation statements)
references
References 56 publications
4
17
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Moreover, individual differences in abilities such as working memory capacity, as well as in general cognitive style, also influence moral judgements (e.g., Bartels, 2008; Bartels & Pizarro, 2011; Moore et al, 2008), as does the presentation of multiple alternatives simultaneously rather than sequentially (Paharia et al, 2009; see also Lombrozo, 2009). The results thus corroborate suggestions that reasoning about moral matters relies on the same cognitive processes as reasoning about non-moral matters (e.g., Białek & De Neys, 2017; Bucciarelli & Johnson-Laird, 2005; Gubbins & Byrne, 2014; Parkinson & Byrne, 2018; Wiegmann & Osman, 2017), such as the construction of a model that causally links the action to the outcome (e.g., Crockett, 2013; Cushman, 2013; Lagnado et al, 2013). Overall, the experiments reported here indicate that people reason differently about moral problems after they have completed cognitively exhausting tasks.…”
Section: Discussionsupporting
confidence: 81%
“…Moreover, individual differences in abilities such as working memory capacity, as well as in general cognitive style, also influence moral judgements (e.g., Bartels, 2008; Bartels & Pizarro, 2011; Moore et al, 2008), as does the presentation of multiple alternatives simultaneously rather than sequentially (Paharia et al, 2009; see also Lombrozo, 2009). The results thus corroborate suggestions that reasoning about moral matters relies on the same cognitive processes as reasoning about non-moral matters (e.g., Białek & De Neys, 2017; Bucciarelli & Johnson-Laird, 2005; Gubbins & Byrne, 2014; Parkinson & Byrne, 2018; Wiegmann & Osman, 2017), such as the construction of a model that causally links the action to the outcome (e.g., Crockett, 2013; Cushman, 2013; Lagnado et al, 2013). Overall, the experiments reported here indicate that people reason differently about moral problems after they have completed cognitively exhausting tasks.…”
Section: Discussionsupporting
confidence: 81%
“…Although we expect to find overall decreases in the OBSERVER's willingness to share information upon learning of an information leakage within the network, we expect the magnitude to differ depending on the attribution of the OFFENDER's intentionality. Indeed, psychological research at the interpersonal level suggests that intentional violations cause observers to assign greater responsibility to the OFFENDER , and they trigger more negative and harsher moral judgments by others than similar unintentional events (Guglielmo & Malle, 2010; Parkinson & Byrne, 2018). Researchers have long acknowledged that employees' behaviors are frequently perceived as representative of the entire organization to outsiders—for example, when it comes to brand impressions after a single employee's actions (Wentzel, 2009).…”
Section: Theoretical Background and Hypothesesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In addition to investigating the functional basis of perceptions of moral wrongness, we examine its severity. The severity of perceived moral wrongness has been linked to the intensity of emotions (see Molho, Tybur, Güler, Balliet, & Hofmann, 2017; Pizarro, 2000; Prinz, 2006; Rozin et al, 1999; Wagemans et al, 2018), intentionality (Cushman, 2008; Parkinson & Byrne, 2018; Russell & Giner-Sorolla, 2011a; Young & Saxe, 2011), moral agency (Gray & Wegner, 2011b), social pressure (Woolfolk, Doris, & Darley, 2006), and moral ethics (Tepe, Cesur, & Sunar, 2017). In line with RRT and Rai and Fiske’s (2012) metarelational approach to (im)moral action, we also suggest that the immorality of an act is not assessed solely with reference to an individual or situation, but that behaviors are evaluated within a community-oriented framework that considers potential implications for future relationships.…”
Section: Metarelational Threatmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The pluralist perspective is mostly highlighted by the Moral Foundation Theory (MFT), which suggests that there are five foundations of morality including harmfulness and impurity, and that the perception of morality varies across cultures and individuals (Graham et al, 2011(Graham et al, , 2013. The addition of the concept of impurity is particularly meaningful in the study of morality (e.g., Chakroff & Young, 2015;Dungan, Chakroff, & Young, 2017;Giner-Sorolla & Chapman, 2016;Horberg, Oveis, Keltner, & Cohen, 2009;Parkinson & Byrne, 2018;Rottman, Kelemen, & Young, 2014;Sabo & Giner-Sorolla, 2017;Vezzali, Brambilla, Giovannini, & Paolo Colucci, 2017;Wagemans, Brandt, & Zeelenberg, 2018;Young & Saxe, 2011) and helps show that various perceptual processes underlie moral judgments. For example, individuals have been shown to be less sensitive to context and the intent of the actor when condemning impure acts than when condemning harmful acts (Chakroff, Dungan, & Young, 2013;Cushman, 2008;Russell & Giner-Sorolla, 2011a;Sousa, Holbrook, & Piazza, 2009;Young & Saxe, 2011).…”
Section: Harm and Impuritymentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation