2013
DOI: 10.1017/s1752971913000237
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Just assassinations

Abstract: I argue that widely accepted just war theory precepts morally allow and require the assassination of politically powerful individuals under some circumstances instead of waging a just war or implementing any other policy such as non-targeted economic sanctions that would very likely severely harm more innocents. While all just war theory precepts permit just assassinations under certain circumstances, proportionality, necessity, and last resort make just assassinations required whenever they would cause severe… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
5
0

Year Published

2015
2015
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
4
3
1

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 13 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 69 publications
0
5
0
Order By: Relevance
“…A one-off attack might be justifi ed if the target is an important and unjust leader and no innocents, or a suffi ciently low number of innocents are killed, according to conditional and contingent pacifi sm respectively. Assassination of an unjust leader currently engaged in harm to innocents is not murder, but rather other-defence (it is bizarre that some hold such killing to be unjust and yet the mass-scale killing in war to be just) (Aloyo 2013;Allen-Gunasekera 2015). 9 Pacifi sts take no issue with harming non-innocent aggressors to save innocents.…”
Section: Targeted Killing Innocents and Proportionalitymentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…A one-off attack might be justifi ed if the target is an important and unjust leader and no innocents, or a suffi ciently low number of innocents are killed, according to conditional and contingent pacifi sm respectively. Assassination of an unjust leader currently engaged in harm to innocents is not murder, but rather other-defence (it is bizarre that some hold such killing to be unjust and yet the mass-scale killing in war to be just) (Aloyo 2013;Allen-Gunasekera 2015). 9 Pacifi sts take no issue with harming non-innocent aggressors to save innocents.…”
Section: Targeted Killing Innocents and Proportionalitymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Targeted killing is one of these alternatives -as the effectiveness and relative harmlessness of targeted killing increases, therefore, the justifi catory threshold for war as a last resort also increases. So the availability of effective targeted killing increases the moral presumption against war (Aloyo 2013;Allen-Gunasekera 2015). But the last resort criterion also applies to targeted killing (albeit, perhaps, in a revised sense).…”
Section: War and 'Force Short Of Force Short Of War'mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Focusing on jus ad bellum , Altman and Wellman ( 2008 ) and Statman ( 2004 , 2012 ) argue that once large-scale military intervention becomes morally permissible, so does targeted killing. Aloyo ( 2013 ) takes this reasoning one step further by speaking of a moral obligation to choose targeted killing over other alternative measures that entail more harm to innocents (see also Strawser 2010 for a similar argument on the use of drones).…”
Section: The Debate On the Use Legitimacy And Impact Of Targeted Kimentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Although the current debate about targeted killing puts an emphasis on the use of unmanned aerial vehicles (or drones), targeted killing involves a large number of methods (Alston, 2010 , p. 4) such as shooting at close or long ranges, stabbing, suffocation, bomb attacks, and contamination with toxic or radioactive substances. Second, the use of lethal violence is intentional (Aloyo, 2013 , p. 349; Altman, 2012 ; Knoepfler, 2010 , p. 470) in the sense that the source has a preconceived plan to kill a human being or group of human beings. This criterion of intentionality sets targeted killing apart from unintentional killing such as “rage-induced or reflex-controlled … killing” (Protevi, 2008 , p. 409) or the incidental or accidental killing of noncombatants in warfare, that is, collateral damage (Coady, 2013 ).…”
Section: A Conceptualization Of Targeted Killingmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Focusing on jus ad bellum, Altman and Wellman (2008) and Statman (2004Statman ( , 2012 argue that once large-scale military intervention becomes morally permissible, so does targeted killing. Aloyo (2013) takes this reasoning one step further by speaking of a moral obligation to choose targeted killing over other alternative measures that entail more harm to innocents (see also Strawser 2010 for a similar argument on the use of drones).…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%