1996
DOI: 10.1007/bf00265256
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Logical consequence: A defense of Tarski

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
24
0
1

Year Published

1996
1996
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
4
4
2

Relationship

0
10

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 30 publications
(25 citation statements)
references
References 18 publications
0
24
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…This judgment, in turn, tends to undermine Etchemendy’s divergence argument, because that argument presupposes that Tarski made the greater error [the mistake of missing the need for domain variation, PM]. (Ray 1996, 630)…”
Section: Sher Corcoran Bach Ray Sagüillomentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This judgment, in turn, tends to undermine Etchemendy’s divergence argument, because that argument presupposes that Tarski made the greater error [the mistake of missing the need for domain variation, PM]. (Ray 1996, 630)…”
Section: Sher Corcoran Bach Ray Sagüillomentioning
confidence: 99%
“…(See, e.g., Etchemendy (1988), Bays (2001), Mancosu (2006). For alternative views see Gómez-Torrente (1996) and Ray (1996).) In my view there are in fact differences between Tarski's notion and the current notion (see e.g.…”
mentioning
confidence: 81%
“…With a firstorder language, the analysis fails unless we add an important modification whose consistency with the original analysis has yet to be explained. 13 Adding this 13 Greg Ray [27] argues that Tarski originally intended to employ varying domains, presumably to prove that the feature is consistent with the original account. But Ray's interpretation is inconsistent with the motivations Tarski gives for the reductive account, with Tarski's explicit description of the account, and with the consequences that he expressly draws from it.…”
Section: Extensional Adequacy Of Tarski's Accountmentioning
confidence: 95%