2022
DOI: 10.1007/s10677-022-10276-x
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

#MeToo & the role of Outright Belief

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1

Citation Types

0
1
0

Year Published

2023
2023
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
3

Relationship

0
3

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 3 publications
(1 citation statement)
references
References 19 publications
0
1
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Notice also that McGrath tends to gloss "being agnostic" as having middling credences, so I can simply run with his account here. (See, e.g., Nelson (2010) for the position that we don't have positive epistemic duties, and see, e.g., Ichikawa (2022), Lloyd (2022), and Simion (2023) for the opposite view) Thus, there seems to be a fundamental tension between our intuitions: in cases like Detective Tupper's, we don't want to say that the agent's belief is justified because they don't appreciate that it is defeated. But in cases like Detective Fletcher's, it seems natural to say that their agnostic attitude is justified if they don't yet appreciate what their evidence supports.…”
Section: A Problem Casementioning
confidence: 99%
“…Notice also that McGrath tends to gloss "being agnostic" as having middling credences, so I can simply run with his account here. (See, e.g., Nelson (2010) for the position that we don't have positive epistemic duties, and see, e.g., Ichikawa (2022), Lloyd (2022), and Simion (2023) for the opposite view) Thus, there seems to be a fundamental tension between our intuitions: in cases like Detective Tupper's, we don't want to say that the agent's belief is justified because they don't appreciate that it is defeated. But in cases like Detective Fletcher's, it seems natural to say that their agnostic attitude is justified if they don't yet appreciate what their evidence supports.…”
Section: A Problem Casementioning
confidence: 99%