2016
DOI: 10.1111/mila.12120
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Motivating the Relevance Approach to Conditionals

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
2
1

Citation Types

0
19
0

Year Published

2016
2016
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
8

Relationship

2
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 23 publications
(19 citation statements)
references
References 37 publications
0
19
0
Order By: Relevance
“…A guiding idea of this tradition is that it constitutes a semantic defect when the antecedent of a conditional is irrelevant to the consequent, as in Edgington's (, p. 267) example: “If Napoleon is dead, Oxford is in England.” In contrast, other accounts will have to set such infelicities aside as pragmatic phenomena that arise due to violations of Gricean norms of informative conversations. Yet, as Skovgaard‐Olsen (forthcoming) argues, such an explanation suffers from the problem that these conditionals lack a standard interpretation, which can be decoded by a minimum of contextual information, whereby they would come out as felicitous even when dealing with individual reasoning. Hence, as they are both defective w.r.t.…”
Section: Ranking Theorymentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…A guiding idea of this tradition is that it constitutes a semantic defect when the antecedent of a conditional is irrelevant to the consequent, as in Edgington's (, p. 267) example: “If Napoleon is dead, Oxford is in England.” In contrast, other accounts will have to set such infelicities aside as pragmatic phenomena that arise due to violations of Gricean norms of informative conversations. Yet, as Skovgaard‐Olsen (forthcoming) argues, such an explanation suffers from the problem that these conditionals lack a standard interpretation, which can be decoded by a minimum of contextual information, whereby they would come out as felicitous even when dealing with individual reasoning. Hence, as they are both defective w.r.t.…”
Section: Ranking Theorymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Moreover, Spohn () lists other candidates for analysis through his account of reason relations such as “although,” ”despite,” and ”because.” Accordingly, “ C although A ” roughly expresses that C was not to be expected, given A , “ C despite A ” likewise expresses negative relevance, and “ C because A ,” inter alia , expresses that C was bound to obtain, given A . Finally, this list has been extended to cover about 30 further utterance modifiers such as “however” and “be that as it may” in Skovgaard‐Olsen (forthcoming).…”
Section: Ranking Theorymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Already contingency accounts for conditionals like (1) (cf. Douven 2008;Skovgaard-Olsen 2016;Skovgaard-Olsen et al 2016). If antecedent and consequent are probabilistically independent, we get DP A C ¼ PðCjAÞ À PðCj:…”
Section: Application 1: the Missing Link Problemmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…One way to account for the oddity of false-link conditionals is to demand the presence of, e.g., an inferential or causal relation between antecedents and consequents for conditionals to be true or acceptable (e.g., Douven 2008;Krzyżanowska et al 2014;Skovgaard-Olsen 2016;Douven et al 2018;van Rooij and Schulz 2018). The connection is then understood as a part of what is said -a conventional, or even truth-conditional content of a conditional, hence sentences such as (1) come out as unacceptable or false.…”
Section: Odd Conditionalsmentioning
confidence: 99%