2019
DOI: 10.1093/pq/pqz029
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

No Theory-Free Lunches in Well-Being Policy

Abstract: Generating an account that can sidestep the disagreement among substantive theories of well-being, while at the same time still providing useful guidance for well-being public policy, would be a significant achievement. Unfortunately, the various attempts to remain agnostic regarding what constitutes well-being fail to either (a) be an account of well-being, (b) provide useful guidance for well-being policy, or (c) avoid relying on a substantive well-being theory. There are no theory-free lunches in well-being… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
8
0

Year Published

2020
2020
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
6
1

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 12 publications
(9 citation statements)
references
References 21 publications
0
8
0
Order By: Relevance
“…think of the issue whether welfare is enhanced by the satisfaction of morally questionable preferences), leading proponents of CAs ground their proposals on philosophical theories of well-being rather than on a reflective equilibrium between philosophical theories and empirical findings, as CAs would prescribe (e.g. Hersch, 2020b; also Alexandrova, 2017a, p. xxxvii, claiming that ‘no choice of a given construct of well-being is intelligent and justified without a theory underpinning it, and building such theories is a distinctly philosophical exercise’). This, in turn, makes it pressing for CAs’ proponents to explicate how exactly the CAs they advocate differ from and improve on the TBAs they criticize and call to replace.…”
Section: Coherentist Approachesmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…think of the issue whether welfare is enhanced by the satisfaction of morally questionable preferences), leading proponents of CAs ground their proposals on philosophical theories of well-being rather than on a reflective equilibrium between philosophical theories and empirical findings, as CAs would prescribe (e.g. Hersch, 2020b; also Alexandrova, 2017a, p. xxxvii, claiming that ‘no choice of a given construct of well-being is intelligent and justified without a theory underpinning it, and building such theories is a distinctly philosophical exercise’). This, in turn, makes it pressing for CAs’ proponents to explicate how exactly the CAs they advocate differ from and improve on the TBAs they criticize and call to replace.…”
Section: Coherentist Approachesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…8 8 A critic of RDL may object that some proponents of CAs acknowledge that the agreement between the best available philosophical theories often enables researchers to significantly constrain the set of plausible constructs and measures of well-being and reach agreement regarding several policies' welfare evaluations (e.g. Hersch, 2020b). This acknowledgement, however, stands in tension with the same authors' insistence that 'we cannot independently answer the question of "what is well-being?"…”
Section: Reformed Division Of Labormentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…being itself, nevertheless constitute outcomes or clear evidence of its existence. Focusing on these markers can therefore suffice for such practical purposes as well-being measurement (Hersch, 2020;Taylor, 2015). Furthermore, assessing well-being sustainability allows one to avoid this challenge, to some degree.…”
Section: Well-beingmentioning
confidence: 99%
“… 1 Philosophers have recently started to ask how scientific tools are apt to provide us with normative guidance (see, for instance, Alexandrova 2018; Hersch 2020). Yet, this debate has, so far, not focused on normative models. …”
mentioning
confidence: 99%