2004
DOI: 10.1353/lan.2004.0195
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

NP-Interpretation and the Structure of Predicates

Abstract: Two classes of intensional transitive verbs affect the interpretation of an indefinite object in the same way that stage- and individual-level predicates affect an indefinite subject. The contrast for objects is instantiated inside the scope of intensionality, that is, VP-internally. I claim that the differentiation of subject positions said to underlie the interpretational contrast for subjects recurs in the VP for objects, inside the domain of intensionality. The internal domain of a transitive verb is there… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
12
0

Year Published

2005
2005
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
7
2

Relationship

1
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 17 publications
(12 citation statements)
references
References 41 publications
0
12
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Here I use v trans from Kratzer 1996 to introduce the external argument, v obj from Jelinek 1998 to introduce the direct object (what Jelinek calls v [trans] ; cf. Bowers 1993, Basilico 1998, and Hallman 2004, and v P to introduce arguments that are marked with various prepositions, following the line of work that introduces oblique arguments as selected by ''applicative'' v's of various sorts (see Anagnostopoulou 2003 andPylkkänen 2008 for recent approaches). The latter sort of v will be coded as selecting the appropriate preposition; for example, v with selects a PP headed by with, and so on.…”
Section: Internal Argument Alternations Under Ellipsismentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Here I use v trans from Kratzer 1996 to introduce the external argument, v obj from Jelinek 1998 to introduce the direct object (what Jelinek calls v [trans] ; cf. Bowers 1993, Basilico 1998, and Hallman 2004, and v P to introduce arguments that are marked with various prepositions, following the line of work that introduces oblique arguments as selected by ''applicative'' v's of various sorts (see Anagnostopoulou 2003 andPylkkänen 2008 for recent approaches). The latter sort of v will be coded as selecting the appropriate preposition; for example, v with selects a PP headed by with, and so on.…”
Section: Internal Argument Alternations Under Ellipsismentioning
confidence: 99%
“…There are many different theories of the nature of this widening and how it arises in the literature (see also Chierchia, 2004Chierchia, , 2013Dayal, 1998Dayal, , 2005Giannakidou, 1998;Krifka, 1995; among many others); however, what is relevant to our analysis is that any can have a particular pragmatic function (domain widening) that is much less available with regular indefinites (i.e., a potato, potatoes). It is well known that particular semantic and/or pragmatic interpretations assigned to a DP can have an effect on its syntactic distribution (Beghelli & Stowell, 1997;Diesing, 1992;Hallman, 2004;Ioup, 1977; among others), thus it is important to determine whether pragmatic widening plays a role in creating the quantitative patterns of Neg-Q/NPI alternation that we observe in synchronic and diachronic corpora.…”
Section: Codingmentioning
confidence: 98%
“…A closer inspection reveals that English is not as different from Arabic as it seems at first glance. The expression most + bare plural is most natural in contexts that also license generic bare plurals (Cooper 1996;Matthewson 2001;Crnič 2010), such as object of a subject experiencer verb (37a) (Erteschik-Shir 1997;Hallman 2004) or subject of an individual level predicate (37b) (Milsark 1974;Carlson 1977a;Diesing 1992). (37) a. John admires most linguists.…”
Section: Quantity Superlative + Indefinite Dependentmentioning
confidence: 99%