2009
DOI: 10.1111/j.1745-8315.2009.00138.x
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

On truth and clinical psychoanalysis

Abstract: Philosophers have enumerated three criteria of truth: coherence, correspondence and pragmatic. I shall define them and examine some of the relations among them. My overarching argument is that these three criteria of truth, when adequately defined, can be seen not to be at odds with each other but to work together in the search for truths in clinical psychoanalysis. I write 'truths' not because I think that truth is relative but because I do not subscribe to any metaphysical theory of absolute truth as in Plat… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
19
0
2

Year Published

2010
2010
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
7
1

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 21 publications
(21 citation statements)
references
References 13 publications
0
19
0
2
Order By: Relevance
“…Important contributions on truth personally selected include: Cavell 1998, Ferenczi 1913, Hanly 1990, Luz 2009, Putnam 1981, Renik 1998, Spence (1982 and Schafer (1992) on Narrative Truth Historical Truth, Stern 1985, Winnicott 1951.…”
Section: Truth Of the Patientmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Important contributions on truth personally selected include: Cavell 1998, Ferenczi 1913, Hanly 1990, Luz 2009, Putnam 1981, Renik 1998, Spence (1982 and Schafer (1992) on Narrative Truth Historical Truth, Stern 1985, Winnicott 1951.…”
Section: Truth Of the Patientmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Focusing on what can be deduced from Matte Blanco’s propositions, I shall begin by recalling that the psychic fact in general, and psychoanalysis in particular (Green 1995, p. 292) are placed between nature and culture and raise questions pertaining both to the sciences of nature and those of the mind (Bell, 2009; Engel, 1996, 1997; Hanly, 2009). Speaking schematically, the first correspond to a hermeneutic approach, and the second to an approach based on observation, even if this dichotomy can be subject to major nuances (Wallerstein, 2009, p. 112).…”
Section: Can We Reduce the Number Of Imaginable Interpretations?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…What counts henceforth, then, is the coherence of the reasoning conducted (for the arguments concerning coherence, concordance and pragmatism as criteria of the truth in analysis, see Hanly, 2009); so this allows us genuine freedom to construct epistemologies in very large numbers. For example, we can develop a theory of the mind which is built on the cornerstone of the theory of the drives ; but equally we might just as well have pointed up the need for adaptation of living organisms in order to understand the primordial rules of the mind and to create another metapsychology.…”
Section: Can We Reduce the Number Of Imaginable Interpretations?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Those who adhere to a reductive epistemological realism in the face of the new criticism (for example Brenner, 1994;Cavell, 1993Cavell, , 1998Friedman, 1997Friedman, , 1999Hanly, 1990Hanly, , 1999Lussier, 1991;Meissner, 2000;Richards, 1999) look upon relational epistemology as a corrective shift of emphasis rather than a qualitatively distinctive way of knowing, and sometimes preface their belief in realistic objectivity with adjectives such as "humble" or "critical." Friedman (1999), for example, writes that "when analysts disclaim their pursuit of a truth about the patient, careful reading usually shows that they are only being humble in its pursuit and acknowledging their inevitable input into what is found" (p. 420).…”
Section: Universalism and Relativity: The Reductive Extremesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The reasoning process Renik advocates makes it impossible to distinguish mythology, religion, and more malevolent ideologies from science, or objectivity from value judgment (Eagle, Wolitzky, & Wakefield, 2001). There would be no "objective" reason for choosing psychoanalysis over other therapies or belief systems (Hanly, 1990;Lussier, 1991). Cavell (1998) makes a similar point when she imagines that the person imbedded in the myopic context and then exposed to the supraordinate one might say: "My claim was made from too narrow a base" (p. 1197).…”
Section: Smith College Studies In Social Workmentioning
confidence: 99%