2006
DOI: 10.1111/j.1468-0017.2006.00288.x
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Ontological Symmetry in Language: A Brief Manifesto

Abstract: :  In the tradition of quantified modal logic, it was assumed that significantly different linguistic systems underlie reference to individuals, to times and to ‘possible worlds’. Various results from recent research in formal semantics suggest that this is not so, and that there is in fact a pervasive symmetry between the linguistic means with which we refer to these three domains. Reference to individuals, times and worlds is uniformly effected through generalized quantifiers, definite descriptions, and pron… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
15
0
1

Year Published

2011
2011
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
5
2
2

Relationship

0
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 39 publications
(16 citation statements)
references
References 56 publications
0
15
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…2 In what follows we will ignore these complexities, however, in order to see what the Lewis-Kratzer view implies for expressions of probability more generally. The general strategy we shall pursue is much in the spirit of the hypothesis of semantic uniformity presented in Schlenker (2006), according to which quantification over times, individuals and worlds, is constrained by general mechanisms that operate alike in the three domains. Following Lewis (1975), Schlenker points out that the sentences ''most of the time, when John comes, Mary is happy'', ''probably, if John comes, Mary will be happy'', and ''most men are wise'' or ''most of the water is poisonous'', are susceptible of essentially the same semantic analysis.…”
Section: If-clauses As Restrictorsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…2 In what follows we will ignore these complexities, however, in order to see what the Lewis-Kratzer view implies for expressions of probability more generally. The general strategy we shall pursue is much in the spirit of the hypothesis of semantic uniformity presented in Schlenker (2006), according to which quantification over times, individuals and worlds, is constrained by general mechanisms that operate alike in the three domains. Following Lewis (1975), Schlenker points out that the sentences ''most of the time, when John comes, Mary is happy'', ''probably, if John comes, Mary will be happy'', and ''most men are wise'' or ''most of the water is poisonous'', are susceptible of essentially the same semantic analysis.…”
Section: If-clauses As Restrictorsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Suppose we replace fictional worlds in our models with fictional possibilities-that is, possible states which do not determinately decide for every sentence whether that sentence is true or false. 36 In doing so, we could reinterpret [Holmes] so that this operator (instead of checking every fictional world compatible with the Holmes stories) simply shifts the world of evaluation to the fictional possibility of the Holmes stories. In making this move, (48) doesn't have the problem stated above-only one Sherlock Holmes is picked out by the use of t sherlock above.…”
Section: Cross-fictional Predication Consider Again (Bilbo)mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…See Partee[31], Cresswell[10], Stone[39], Kratzer[23],King [21], Schlenker[36], and Schaffer[35] for a discussion.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…We are therefore able to capture the systematic anaphoric and quantificational parallels between the individual and modal domains argued for in Frank (1996), van Rooy (1998), Stone (1999), Bittner (2001) and Schlenker (2005) among others (building on Partee 1973Partee , 1984. (94) John x thinks w ½ w that he x will w catch a y fish and he x hopes w ¾ w,w ½ I will w ¾ grill it y tonight.…”
Section: Quantificational Dependencies Cross-sententially: Quantificamentioning
confidence: 99%