1974
DOI: 10.1007/bf02379302
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Ought implies can and deontic logic

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2

Citation Types

0
4
0

Year Published

2007
2007
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
6
1

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 12 publications
(4 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
0
4
0
Order By: Relevance
“…The view that obligations to promote global justice, such as helping others in need depends on our abilities is motivated by the longstanding ethical principle that "ought implies can". Support for this principle weaves its way through the history of western philosophy and is accepted by most contemporary anglophone philosophers (Kant 1998;Littlejohn 2012;Moore 1922;Hare 1965;Van Fraassen 1973;Dahl 1974;Vranas 2007;Copp 2008;Cicero and Edmonds 1856). Although the principle is glossed in many forms, the basic idea is that inability rules out obligation.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The view that obligations to promote global justice, such as helping others in need depends on our abilities is motivated by the longstanding ethical principle that "ought implies can". Support for this principle weaves its way through the history of western philosophy and is accepted by most contemporary anglophone philosophers (Kant 1998;Littlejohn 2012;Moore 1922;Hare 1965;Van Fraassen 1973;Dahl 1974;Vranas 2007;Copp 2008;Cicero and Edmonds 1856). Although the principle is glossed in many forms, the basic idea is that inability rules out obligation.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…A widely accepted view in western philosophy is that moral obligations entail the ability to fulfill them, often glossed in the slogan that Bought implies can^ (Copp 2008;Dahl 1974;Feldman 1986;Fischer 2003;Hare 1965;Howard-Snyder 2006;Moore 1922;Streumer 2003;Van Fraassen 1973). This longstanding principle can be traced from ancient philosophy (Cicero: Bpromises are not binding when the performance is impossible,^1856) and modern philosophy (Kant: Bduty commands nothing but what we can do,^1793/1998) to contemporary normative ethics (Vranas: Ban agent at a given time has an objective, pro tanto obligation to do only what the agent at that time has the ability and opportunity to do,^2007: 167), and social political philosophy (O'Neill: Binstitutions and individuals can have obligations if but only if they have adequate capabilities to fulfill or discharge those obligations,^2004: 251).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…It might of course be that saving the antique is indeed supererogatory. However, in principle, it is possible to advance a new example where the source action is not supererogatory while retaining the same argumentative structure as that in Kolodny's original example.17 For further a discussion concerning 'ought implies can' see(Austin 1956;Carlson 1999;Dahl 1974;Howard-Snyder 1997;King 2014;Stocker 1971;Vranas 2007).18 This might depend on one's view in Jackson-style cases, such as the doctor who can give one of three possible drugs to a sick patient. One of the drugs will partially cure the patient.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%