2008
DOI: 10.1007/s10670-008-9102-5
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Pi on Earth, or Mathematics in the Real World

Abstract: We explore aspects of an experimental approach to mathematical proof, most notably number crunching, or the verification of subsequent particular cases of universal propositions. Since the rise of the computer age, this technique has indeed conquered practice, although it implies the abandonment of the ideal of absolute certainty. It seems that also in mathematical research, the qualitative criterion of effectiveness, i.e. to reach one's goals, gets increasingly balanced against the quantitative one of efficie… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
5
0

Year Published

2008
2008
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
4
3

Relationship

1
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 8 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 21 publications
0
5
0
Order By: Relevance
“…One cannot be expected to make sound conclusions about how we come to be justified in believing scientific theories without taking notice of how scientists go about justifying their own theories (and indeed go about experimenting generally). The same can be said for mathematics, and the last 20 years has seen a far greater appreciation of mathematical epistemology by looking in detail at the practice of working mathematicians [see, for example, Giaquinto (2007), Van Bendegem (2003), and Van Kerkhove and Van Bendegem (2008]. The assumption underlying all of these uses of a practice-based approach to the epistemology of a particular field is that scientists and mathematicians are generally very good at recognising what constitutes suitable evidence for a theory within their field, and what the plausible means are to justify a proposition or theory.…”
Section: Learning From Practicementioning
confidence: 99%
“…One cannot be expected to make sound conclusions about how we come to be justified in believing scientific theories without taking notice of how scientists go about justifying their own theories (and indeed go about experimenting generally). The same can be said for mathematics, and the last 20 years has seen a far greater appreciation of mathematical epistemology by looking in detail at the practice of working mathematicians [see, for example, Giaquinto (2007), Van Bendegem (2003), and Van Kerkhove and Van Bendegem (2008]. The assumption underlying all of these uses of a practice-based approach to the epistemology of a particular field is that scientists and mathematicians are generally very good at recognising what constitutes suitable evidence for a theory within their field, and what the plausible means are to justify a proposition or theory.…”
Section: Learning From Practicementioning
confidence: 99%
“…rivalrous and excludable) good that can form the basis for an incentive structure that motivates scientists, leading to them working harder and dividing up their efforts across different problems and methodologies (Merton 1957, Zollman 2018. The priority rule for publications is written into scientific history by discoveries which are named 1 Fallis (1997) and Van Kerkhove and Van Bendegem (2008) have footnotes on the Classification Theorem, but don't discuss it in depth. Fallis (2003) and Johansen and Misfeldt (2016) mention it as a potential parallel to the problems raised by the Four Colour Theorem.…”
Section: The Role Of Proofs In Mathematical Practicementioning
confidence: 99%
“…We believe that, although they have been overlooked, massively collaborative efforts such as the Classification of Finite Simple Groups pose similar challenges to the core properties of proof, particularly to the way these properties have been framed in individualistic terms. 1 1 Fallis (1997) and Van Kerkhove and Van Bendegem (2008) have footnotes on the Classification Theorem, but don't discuss it in depth. Fallis (2003) and Johansen and Misfeldt (2016) mention it as a potential parallel to the problems raised by the Four Colour Theorem.…”
Section: Conceptions Of Proofsmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…A complementary approach which does take the practice of computer-assisted mathematics more seriously seems necessary in order to get a more balanced account of the impact of the computer on (the philosophy of) mathematics. This has already been argued to some extent by (van Kerkhove and van Bendegem 2008) where it is stated that we should account for the practices underpinning formal proofs, including the use of experimental methods (Idem, p. 434):…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%