2002
DOI: 10.1037/h0087385
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Probability matching: Encouraging optimal responding in humans.

Abstract: Two hundred undergraduate students participated in a repeated-trials binary choice procedure in which choice of one outcome was correct on 75% of trials. Subjects received 192 trials and were divided into five conditions: (1) control; (2) subjects were given the actual probabilities; (3) subjects were told if they did well they could leave early; (4) competition condition;(5) midway through the task subjects were asked to recommend a strategy for another subject. Hall of the subjects in each group were told th… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

4
46
0
1

Year Published

2003
2003
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
7
2

Relationship

2
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 52 publications
(51 citation statements)
references
References 15 publications
4
46
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…However, despite this explicit representation, subject behavior was similar to that in the even pieces, computer stops condition, with significantly fewer choices toward the better option than in the uneven pieces, subject stops condition. This failure to maximize is consistent with previous work by Fantino and Esfandiari (4), which demonstrated suboptimal choice behavior even when subjects were explicitly told the overall reward probabilities, and also with the general fact that knowledge of the overall reward probabilities is typically insufficient to compute the optimal policy (i.e., it is only in the very special case where options are perfectly coupled and outcomes are completely independent across time that the overall reward probabilities are sufficient to compute the optimal policy).…”
Section: Resultssupporting
confidence: 92%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…However, despite this explicit representation, subject behavior was similar to that in the even pieces, computer stops condition, with significantly fewer choices toward the better option than in the uneven pieces, subject stops condition. This failure to maximize is consistent with previous work by Fantino and Esfandiari (4), which demonstrated suboptimal choice behavior even when subjects were explicitly told the overall reward probabilities, and also with the general fact that knowledge of the overall reward probabilities is typically insufficient to compute the optimal policy (i.e., it is only in the very special case where options are perfectly coupled and outcomes are completely independent across time that the overall reward probabilities are sufficient to compute the optimal policy).…”
Section: Resultssupporting
confidence: 92%
“…This is an exceptionally consistent effect known as "probability matching." It has been replicated in dozens of laboratories, under myriad task conditions, and is extremely robust, persisting for thousands of trials (1)(2)(3)(4)(5)(6)(7)(8)(9)(10)(11)(12)(13)(14)(15). Most theories treat this behavior as a fundamental failure of rational decision making.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Probability matching is typically observed in both variants, but it tends to occur less when the probabilities are known from the start (Fantino & Esfandiari, 2002) and/or when the generating process can be identified as random (Morse & Runquist, 1960;Peterson & Ulehla, 1965). Instead of examining choice in a two-stage probability learning paradigm like the one used in Experiment 2, an alternative approach might be to apply a descriptive version of the problem to fully relieve participants from the onus of having to learn about outcome probabilities.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Performance in probability-learning tasks can be improved by emphasizing that trials are independent or that probabilities are fixed. For instance, the rate of optimal responding increases when participants are told the actual probabilities for each option (Fantino & Esfandiari, 2002), when the task is presented as a gambling task rather than a problem-solving task (Goodnow, 1955), and when participants roll a die instead of seeing written sequences of outcomes (Peterson & Ulehla, 1965). The success of these interventions, which emphasize trial independence and stationary payoffs, implies that participants may not necessarily assume these features to be true when they approach the task.…”
Section: Models Of Sequential Choice Applied To Nonstationary Payoffsmentioning
confidence: 99%