1977
DOI: 10.1016/s0049-237x(08)71124-8
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Proof Theory: Some Applications of Cut-Elimination

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
94
0

Year Published

1985
1985
2012
2012

Publication Types

Select...
5
3

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 130 publications
(94 citation statements)
references
References 7 publications
0
94
0
Order By: Relevance
“…So in order to perform the modus ponens under the no-counterexample interpretation one needs exactly the same use of bar recursion B 0,1 as discussed in 4.3 above (for a detailed discussion see [60]). For the special case (+), the no-counterexample interpretation yields results as strong as the combination of negative translation with functional interpretation but to verify the soundness of the former for a given system one either has to prove the soundness of the latter or to apply a suitable form of ε-substitution or cut-elimination ( [76,77,97]) which destroys the modularity of the interpretation.…”
Section: Discussion Of the Results Of The Comparisonmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…So in order to perform the modus ponens under the no-counterexample interpretation one needs exactly the same use of bar recursion B 0,1 as discussed in 4.3 above (for a detailed discussion see [60]). For the special case (+), the no-counterexample interpretation yields results as strong as the combination of negative translation with functional interpretation but to verify the soundness of the former for a given system one either has to prove the soundness of the latter or to apply a suitable form of ε-substitution or cut-elimination ( [76,77,97]) which destroys the modularity of the interpretation.…”
Section: Discussion Of the Results Of The Comparisonmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In fact, the original proof of the no-counterexample interpretation (based on a different description of the type-2 functionals in T as the α(< ε 0 )-recursive functionals of type 2) as given in [76,77] was based on the ε-substitution method developed in [1] and so rather on a form of cut-elimination than established as a proof interpretation. A proof by direct use of cut-elimination was given subsequently in [97]. In fact, [34] shows that the no-counterexample interpretation was clearly anticipated by Gödel's analysis of Gentzen's consistency proof for PA based on cut-elimination.…”
Section: Theorem 32 (Program Extraction By D-interpretation)mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…By employing a partial truth predicate for Π 0 n -formulae and transfinite induction up to ε k+1 , one shows that PA + TI(≺ ε ω ) A (cf. [10]). …”
Section: Lemmamentioning
confidence: 99%
“…[78]). There also is asimple (but less constructive) alternative model-theoretic proof based on compactness theorem.…”
Section: Provably Total Computable Functions and 1-consistencymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…We rely on the standard cut-elimination techniques for a variant of sequent calculus due to Tait that is presented, for example, in Schwichtenberg [78]. Formulas in Tait's calculus are constructed as in the first order logic from atomic formulas and their negations by the connectives ∧, ∨ and the quantifiers ∀, ∃.…”
Section: Tait Calculusmentioning
confidence: 99%