1979
DOI: 10.5840/monist197962220
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Reference and Contingency

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
91
0
4

Year Published

2001
2001
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
5
4
1

Relationship

0
10

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 244 publications
(95 citation statements)
references
References 2 publications
0
91
0
4
Order By: Relevance
“…These two senses are familiar from the distinction between deep and shallow necessity drawn by Evans (1979) and Davies and Humberstone (1980). Slightly simplified, a sentence φ is shallowly necessary if and only if:…”
Section: Contingency and Invariancementioning
confidence: 99%
“…These two senses are familiar from the distinction between deep and shallow necessity drawn by Evans (1979) and Davies and Humberstone (1980). Slightly simplified, a sentence φ is shallowly necessary if and only if:…”
Section: Contingency and Invariancementioning
confidence: 99%
“…(AK) both explains and legitimates this systematic tendency, in a very tidy way. Evans (1985) and Hawthorne (2002), for example, do not cite (4) as an example of the contingent a priori, but rather (19).…”
Section: Conditionalsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For example, consider Evans' descriptive name 'Julius', introduced for whoever invented the zip (Evans 1979). The primary intension of 'Julius' picks out whoever invented the zip in a given scenario, while its secondary intension picks out the actual inventor (William C. Whitworth) in all worlds.…”
Section: Two-dimensional Semanticsmentioning
confidence: 99%