2017
DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12237
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Schopenhauer on the Rights of Animals

Abstract: I argue that Schopenhauer's ascription of (moral) rights to animals flows naturally from his distinctive analysis of the concept of a right. In contrast to those who regard rights as fundamental and then cast wrongdoing as a matter of violating rights, he takes wrong (Unrecht) to be the more fundamental notion and defines the concept of a right (Recht) in its terms. He then offers an account of wrongdoing which makes it plausible to suppose that at least many animals can be wronged and thus, by extension, have… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
4
0

Year Published

2019
2019
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
6
2

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 8 publications
(4 citation statements)
references
References 31 publications
0
4
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Moral distress is defined as "knowing the right thing to do but being unable to do so due to various constraints" (Jameton 1984;O'Byrne et al 2021;Garrett 2020;Dzau et al 2020;Lin 2020;Morley 2019;Wiggins & Wilbanks 2019;Bursztajn 1998). Although studies on this issue also use terms such as 'moral injury' (e.g., Borges et al 2020;Williamson et al 2020), 'moral suffering,' 'moral anguish' (Godshall 2021), and 'moral harm' equivalently here, the scope of the latter experiences goes beyond professional (particularly medical and judicial) and even human contexts (e.g., Puryear 2017). In this article, we ponder moral distress, and it is precisely what we have been investigating.…”
Section: Theorising Moral Distressmentioning
confidence: 96%
“…Moral distress is defined as "knowing the right thing to do but being unable to do so due to various constraints" (Jameton 1984;O'Byrne et al 2021;Garrett 2020;Dzau et al 2020;Lin 2020;Morley 2019;Wiggins & Wilbanks 2019;Bursztajn 1998). Although studies on this issue also use terms such as 'moral injury' (e.g., Borges et al 2020;Williamson et al 2020), 'moral suffering,' 'moral anguish' (Godshall 2021), and 'moral harm' equivalently here, the scope of the latter experiences goes beyond professional (particularly medical and judicial) and even human contexts (e.g., Puryear 2017). In this article, we ponder moral distress, and it is precisely what we have been investigating.…”
Section: Theorising Moral Distressmentioning
confidence: 96%
“…For example, he states that the Neminem Principle identifies which actions have moral worth (moralischen Werth) (BM, 139), which would blur the first distinction from the previous section. Similarly, Schopenhauer elsewhere says that wrongness hinges on an agent's aim in acting (WWR 1, 364), which contradicts his definition of wrongness in terms of harm or the boundaries of another's will (though see Puryear 2017). Even on a charitable reading, therefore, we must grant that Schopenhauer's presentation of his normative ethics is messy.…”
Section: Moral Dimensionsmentioning
confidence: 98%
“…This first criticism thus falls flat. 5 4 I discuss various aspects of his positive account in Puryear (2017) and Puryear (forthcoming). 5 Schopenhauer's critique in On the Basis of Morality focuses specifically on the Groundwork (BM §3, 119); it is therefore beside the point whether in the second Critique Kant effectively renounces the argument from Groundwork III and instead merely posits the moral law as a "fact of reason" (CPrR 5:31,47).…”
Section: Kant's Petitio Principiimentioning
confidence: 99%