1993
DOI: 10.1037/0278-7393.19.2.414
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Selective associations and causality judgments: Presence of a strong causal factor may reduce judgments of a weaker one.

Abstract: This document is copyrighted by the American Psychological Association or one of its allied publishers.This article is intended solely for the personal use of the individual user and is not to be disseminated broadly.

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

15
169
2
6

Year Published

1994
1994
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
8
1
1

Relationship

0
10

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 121 publications
(192 citation statements)
references
References 50 publications
15
169
2
6
Order By: Relevance
“…In fact, the data from several articles that claimed to show that people were poor reasoners because they deviated far from D P when reasoning about multiple causes of effects (e.g., Baker, Mercier, Vallée-Tourangeau, Frank, & Pan, 1993;Chapman, 1991;Chapman & Robbins, 1990;Price & Yates, 1993 can be reanalyzed to show that people seem to be using the "smarter" conditional contingency strategy (Cheng, 1993;Melz, Cheng, Holyoak, & Waldmann, 1993;Shanks, 1993Shanks, , 1995Spellman, 1993Spellman, , 1996aSpellman, , 1996b Schaller and colleagues (Schaller, 1992a(Schaller, , 1992bSchaller & O' Brien, 1992) have investigated the use of something akin to conditionalization-what he calls "intuitive analysis of covariance"-in tasks that do not involve causal reasoning. For instance, in a study that is reminiscent of our baseball example, subjects were presented with information about the racquetball prowess of two potential doubles partners.…”
Section: Simpson's Paradox: the Mathematical Problem Of Differing Basmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In fact, the data from several articles that claimed to show that people were poor reasoners because they deviated far from D P when reasoning about multiple causes of effects (e.g., Baker, Mercier, Vallée-Tourangeau, Frank, & Pan, 1993;Chapman, 1991;Chapman & Robbins, 1990;Price & Yates, 1993 can be reanalyzed to show that people seem to be using the "smarter" conditional contingency strategy (Cheng, 1993;Melz, Cheng, Holyoak, & Waldmann, 1993;Shanks, 1993Shanks, , 1995Spellman, 1993Spellman, , 1996aSpellman, , 1996b Schaller and colleagues (Schaller, 1992a(Schaller, , 1992bSchaller & O' Brien, 1992) have investigated the use of something akin to conditionalization-what he calls "intuitive analysis of covariance"-in tasks that do not involve causal reasoning. For instance, in a study that is reminiscent of our baseball example, subjects were presented with information about the racquetball prowess of two potential doubles partners.…”
Section: Simpson's Paradox: the Mathematical Problem Of Differing Basmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The impact of the SS prior is that when two (or more) possible generative causes of E cooccur and one cause has a stronger statistical link to E than the other, the presence of the stronger cause will tend to reduce the judged strength of the weaker one (cf. Baker, Mercier, Vallée-Tourangeau, Frank, & Pan, 1993;Busemeyer, Myung, & McDaniel, 1993). Figure 3 shows an example of the posterior distribution of w 1 obtained given contingency data of p(e ϩ |c Ϫ ) ϭ 12/16 and p(e ϩ |c ϩ ) ϭ 16/16, based on either SS or uniform priors (see Appendix A for derivation).…”
Section: Generic Priors For Sparse and Strong Causesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Arcediano, Ortega, and Matute (1996) developed the "Martians" game to explore classical conditioning using Martians and explosions as stimuli (see also Baeyens et al, 2005;Blanco, Matute, & Vadillo, 2010;Franssen, Clarysse, Beckers, van Vooren, & Baeyens, 2010). Gamelike tasks have been used to study instrumental learning with stimuli presented as balloons that must be shot from the sky (Krageloh, Zapanta, Shepherd, & Landon, 2010), minefields to be navigated (Baker, Mercier, Vallee-Tourangeau, Frank, & Pan, 1993), or a host of similar examples (Lie, Harper, & Hunt, 2009;Molet, Jozefowiez, & Miller, 2010;Paredes-Olay, Abad, Gamez, & Rosas, 2002;Stokes & Balsam, 2001;Stokes & Harrison, 2002). Discrimination and generalization learning have been presented as melodies that participants must classify as belonging to different composers (Artigas, Chamizio, & Peris, 2001) or as torpedoes to be launched at certain flying objects but not others (Nelson & Sanjuan, 2008;Nelson, Sanjuan, Vadillo-Ruiz, & Perez, 2011).…”
Section: Gaming-up Experimentsmentioning
confidence: 99%