2016
DOI: 10.1111/phc3.12347
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Some Varieties of Metaethical Relativism

Abstract: This opinionated survey article discusses a relativist view in metaethics that we can call Appraiser-standard Relativism. According to this view, the truth value of moral judgments varies depending on the moral standard (the norms or values, etc.) of the appraiserthat is, someone who makes or assesses the judgments. On this view, when two persons judge that, say, lying is always morally wrong; one of the judgments might be true and the other false. The paper presents various forms of this view, contrasts it ag… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2020
2020
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
3
1

Relationship

0
4

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 4 publications
(3 citation statements)
references
References 50 publications
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Other responses are based on metalinguistic negotiations (see Sundell (2013 and, Khoo and Knobe (2016), Silk (2016: 125-6 and 2017: 214 and 222-5 (though see Finlay (2017)) and Sodoma (2021: §5)), proposition clouds (Suikkanen 2019), or rejecting our semantic intuitions about disagreements (see Rovane (2013: 30 and 113), Velleman (2015: 55 and 76), Finlay (2017 and 202) and for a discussion see Sodoma (2021: §3.1)). For an overview, see Francén Olinder (2016), Finlay (2017), andRowland (2021: §3.3). account of the connection to motivation is along the right lines, we know that in their exchange, even if A and B are talking about different properties of typing thank-you notes, they are also guaranteed to have conflicting motivational attitudes towards those actions.…”
Section: Different Contextualists Can Then Formulate In Different Way...mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…Other responses are based on metalinguistic negotiations (see Sundell (2013 and, Khoo and Knobe (2016), Silk (2016: 125-6 and 2017: 214 and 222-5 (though see Finlay (2017)) and Sodoma (2021: §5)), proposition clouds (Suikkanen 2019), or rejecting our semantic intuitions about disagreements (see Rovane (2013: 30 and 113), Velleman (2015: 55 and 76), Finlay (2017 and 202) and for a discussion see Sodoma (2021: §3.1)). For an overview, see Francén Olinder (2016), Finlay (2017), andRowland (2021: §3.3). account of the connection to motivation is along the right lines, we know that in their exchange, even if A and B are talking about different properties of typing thank-you notes, they are also guaranteed to have conflicting motivational attitudes towards those actions.…”
Section: Different Contextualists Can Then Formulate In Different Way...mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…5)). For overviews of the issues covered here, see alsoRachels (1991),Wong (1991),Dreier (2006), MacFarlane (2012),Sturgeon (2010), Francén Olinder (2016,Silk (2018),Stojanovic (2018) andBjörnsson (2021).…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This is consistent because the error theorist can deny both that "not permissible" entails "impermissible" and that "not impermissible" entails "permissible"(Olson, 2014, p. 14).17 Error theorists would thus deny that normative vagueness exists(Dougherty, 2018, p. 191).18 For surveys, seeRachels, 1991, Wong, 1991, Dreier, 2009, and Francén Olinder, 2016 …”
mentioning
confidence: 98%