2014
DOI: 10.1017/s0960129514000450
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Specifying Peirce's law in classical realizability

Abstract: This paper deals with the specification problem in classical realizability (such as introduced by Krivine (2009 Panoramas et synthéses27)), which is to characterize the universal realizers of a given formula by their computational behaviour. After recalling the framework of classical realizability, we present the problem in the general case and illustrate it with some examples. In the rest of the paper, we focus on Peirce's law, and present two game-theoretic characterizations of its universal realizers. First… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
15
0

Year Published

2016
2016
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
3
2

Relationship

2
3

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 6 publications
(15 citation statements)
references
References 17 publications
0
15
0
Order By: Relevance
“…We will rephrase the gametheoretic framework of the first author Ph.D. thesis (Guillermo 2008), to provide a game-theoretic characterization G 1 that is both complete and adequate, in the particular case where the underlying calculus contains infinitely many interaction constants. However, this hypothesis -that is crucial in our proof of completeness -is known to be incompatible with the presence of instructions such as quote or eq (Guillermo and Miquel 2014), which allow us to distinguish syntactically λ c terms that are computationally equivalent. We exhibit in Section 6.3 a wild realizer that uses these instructions and does not suit as a winning strategy for G 1 , proving that G 1 is no more complete in this case.…”
Section: Specifying Arithmetical Formulaementioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…We will rephrase the gametheoretic framework of the first author Ph.D. thesis (Guillermo 2008), to provide a game-theoretic characterization G 1 that is both complete and adequate, in the particular case where the underlying calculus contains infinitely many interaction constants. However, this hypothesis -that is crucial in our proof of completeness -is known to be incompatible with the presence of instructions such as quote or eq (Guillermo and Miquel 2014), which allow us to distinguish syntactically λ c terms that are computationally equivalent. We exhibit in Section 6.3 a wild realizer that uses these instructions and does not suit as a winning strategy for G 1 , proving that G 1 is no more complete in this case.…”
Section: Specifying Arithmetical Formulaementioning
confidence: 99%
“…Furthermore, as stated in the paper on Peirce's Law (Guillermo and Miquel 2014), the presence of instructions such as quote (defined in Section 2.3) makes the problem still more subtle. We will deal with this particular case in Section 7.…”
Section: The Specification Problemmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For further details about these definitions we refer to Guillermo and Miquel (2014). P. †/ mapping a k-tuple to a set of stacks.…”
Section: Realizability Interpretationmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…24 As explained in Naibo et al (2015), the approach undertaken by untyped proof theory differs from the usual techniques adopted in standard proof theory, as it considers a set of objects -the paraproofs -which is much larger than the set of proofs. 23 Although the pole is sometimes defined from a set of processes which could be understood as a notion of termination (see Guillermo and Miquel 2014). 22 Notice, however, that one defines the interpretation of linear logic formulas, and not classical logic formulas, as it will be clarified below.…”
Section: Classical Realizability As An Untyped Proof Theorymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…See for instance[27] about witness extraction or[12,13] about specification problems 4. For instance, one way to realize the axiom of dependent choice in classical realizability is by means of an extra instruction quote[18] 5.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%