2010
DOI: 10.1017/s1360674310000158
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The functions ofweorðanand its loss in the past tense in Old and Middle English

Abstract: In this article, I relate the loss of weorðan in the past tense to the loss of an Old English grammatical subsystem that encouraged the expression of narrative by bounded sentence constructions. This type of construction represents a situation as reaching its goal or endpoint, and serves to mark progress in a narrative (e.g. then he walked over to the other side). Instead of this system, from Middle English onwards a mixed system emerges with differently structured bounded sentence constructions as well as, in… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

1
8
0

Year Published

2014
2014
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
4
1
1

Relationship

1
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 33 publications
(9 citation statements)
references
References 28 publications
1
8
0
Order By: Relevance
“…This suggests that passive constructions played an enabling rather than a leading part in the disappearance of weorðan from English: the lack of grammaticalization in the passive meant that the loss of this lexeme (along with its replacement by others, notably becuman and weaxan ) could occur without great disruption to the capacity of the language to denote passive situations. This would be compatible with an account in which the trigger for the loss of weorðan came, not from the passive, but from elsewhere, for example from the blurring of the early OE semantic distinction between weorðan ‘become’ and geweorðan ‘happen’ (see fn 19), or from the shift the language from ‘bounded’ to ‘unbounded’ sentences (see Petré ).…”
Section: Summary Of Results and Discussionsupporting
confidence: 63%
See 3 more Smart Citations
“…This suggests that passive constructions played an enabling rather than a leading part in the disappearance of weorðan from English: the lack of grammaticalization in the passive meant that the loss of this lexeme (along with its replacement by others, notably becuman and weaxan ) could occur without great disruption to the capacity of the language to denote passive situations. This would be compatible with an account in which the trigger for the loss of weorðan came, not from the passive, but from elsewhere, for example from the blurring of the early OE semantic distinction between weorðan ‘become’ and geweorðan ‘happen’ (see fn 19), or from the shift the language from ‘bounded’ to ‘unbounded’ sentences (see Petré ).…”
Section: Summary Of Results and Discussionsupporting
confidence: 63%
“…Mitchell , i , 331), weorðan occurs with significantly greater frequency in the preterite than in the praesens (χ²(2) = 35.24, p < 0.001). This may be connected with the observed use of weorðan as a frequent structural device in narrative sequences (see Petré ); such narrative structures would naturally be most frequent in the preterite. The variation between praesentia and non‐finite forms is not statistically significant (χ²(1) = 1.92, p > 0.05).…”
Section: Resultsmentioning
confidence: 93%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…); this is represented schematically in Figure 10 Th e hypothesis that there has been a structural increase in unbounded construal, while still somewhat speculative, seems worth examining, as it makes it possible to relate a number of superfi cially local and unrelated changes that take place in the English language around the same time. Changes that have been linked to this shift so far have been the loss of verb-second, which is generally considered to be the trigger that got everything moving (Los 2009, Los 2012, the decrease of time adverbials in clause-initial position (van Kemenade & Westergaard 2012, Petré 2014, the loss of the copula of change weorðan 'become' , by its association with verb-second word order (Petré 2010), unusual passives and cleft s (Los 2012), or the progressive (Petré accepted).…”
Section: Absolute Constructions As Further Evidence For a Typologicalmentioning
confidence: 99%