The Constitution of Equality 2008
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198297475.003.0008
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The Limits to Democratic Authority

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

1
51
0
5

Year Published

2013
2013
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
8
1

Relationship

0
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 64 publications
(57 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
1
51
0
5
Order By: Relevance
“…First, legitimacy standards are grounded in special procedural (Rawls, 1996), substantive (Erman, 2015) or non-ideal (Valentini, 2012) moral principles , posited as more fundamental than the value of particular institutional standards themselves. For example, it is commonly claimed that liberal and democratic standards generate legitimacy by helping institutions satisfy moral demands for individual autonomy (Valentini, 2012) or political equality (Christiano, 2008); similarly, consequentialist moral principles are invoked as grounds for ‘output’ legitimacy standards (Keohane, 2011; Scharpf, 1999). Such ‘moralist’ (Williams, 2005) accounts appeal to normative reasons articulated by moral philosophers; but in many global institutional contexts, philosophers’ moral principles are rejected by many political agents whose support is at issue – due to repudiation of cosmopolitan morality (Walzer, 1980) or the view that the scope of liberal and democratic moral principles is limited to domestic (Miller, 2010; Rawls, 2001) or otherwise circumscribed (Maffettone and Ulas, 2019) institutional spheres.…”
Section: Legitimacy and The Normative Grounds Of World Ordermentioning
confidence: 99%
“…First, legitimacy standards are grounded in special procedural (Rawls, 1996), substantive (Erman, 2015) or non-ideal (Valentini, 2012) moral principles , posited as more fundamental than the value of particular institutional standards themselves. For example, it is commonly claimed that liberal and democratic standards generate legitimacy by helping institutions satisfy moral demands for individual autonomy (Valentini, 2012) or political equality (Christiano, 2008); similarly, consequentialist moral principles are invoked as grounds for ‘output’ legitimacy standards (Keohane, 2011; Scharpf, 1999). Such ‘moralist’ (Williams, 2005) accounts appeal to normative reasons articulated by moral philosophers; but in many global institutional contexts, philosophers’ moral principles are rejected by many political agents whose support is at issue – due to repudiation of cosmopolitan morality (Walzer, 1980) or the view that the scope of liberal and democratic moral principles is limited to domestic (Miller, 2010; Rawls, 2001) or otherwise circumscribed (Maffettone and Ulas, 2019) institutional spheres.…”
Section: Legitimacy and The Normative Grounds Of World Ordermentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Second, people tend to be cognitively biased towards their own well-being, conception of the good and the role they play in their financial success (cf. Christiano 2008, pp. 58–60; Halliday 2018, pp.…”
Section: The Efficacy Objectionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…More precisely, the focus is on what he calls ‘liberal equality’: the idea that each citizen must be treated equally by the formal institutions of democracy. This is also a core idea for Christiano (1996, 2008), who discusses and develops its deeper philosophical foundations. McGann (2013) insists that once we are committed to liberal equality – which we should be as democrats – we can understand certain institutional choices as logical requirements and thus in a quasi-objective manner.…”
Section: Political Equality and Fair Representationmentioning
confidence: 99%