2015
DOI: 10.1007/s13164-015-0244-5
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The Problematic Welfare Standards of Behavioral Paternalism

Abstract: Behavioral paternalism raises deep concerns that do not arise in traditional welfare economics. These concerns stem from behavioral paternalism's acceptance of the defining axioms of neoclassical rationality for normative purposes, despite having rejected them as positive descriptions of reality. We argue (1) that behavioral paternalists have indeed accepted neoclassical rationality axioms as a welfare standard; (2) that economists historically adopted these axioms not for their normative plausibility, but for… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
32
0
1

Year Published

2015
2015
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
5
5

Relationship

0
10

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 79 publications
(33 citation statements)
references
References 34 publications
0
32
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…Instead of applying a case-specific welfare analysis as for externalities, Thaler and Sunstein (2008) set the weight for System 1's interests to zero throughout. The conflict between the two selves in forming preferences is not solved but replaced by an assumption, which, in perfect circularity, requires System 2 to be (at least close to) the Homo oeconomicus: Only those preferences should be taken into account that System 2 reaches after being removed from stimuli, having ample time to deliberate and being able to rationally analyse the options (Infante et al, 2016;Rebonato, 2012;Schnellenbach & Schubert, 2015;Whitman & Rizzo, 2015). 15 The use of the two-system process of reasoning in this context is problematic for multiple reasons.…”
Section: Conceptual Concernsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Instead of applying a case-specific welfare analysis as for externalities, Thaler and Sunstein (2008) set the weight for System 1's interests to zero throughout. The conflict between the two selves in forming preferences is not solved but replaced by an assumption, which, in perfect circularity, requires System 2 to be (at least close to) the Homo oeconomicus: Only those preferences should be taken into account that System 2 reaches after being removed from stimuli, having ample time to deliberate and being able to rationally analyse the options (Infante et al, 2016;Rebonato, 2012;Schnellenbach & Schubert, 2015;Whitman & Rizzo, 2015). 15 The use of the two-system process of reasoning in this context is problematic for multiple reasons.…”
Section: Conceptual Concernsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For example, some critics worry that systematic government nudging might fail to reliably pick out the right or best option, might be exploited for perfectionist or even illicit ends, and lead us onto a slippery slope towards 14 Such nudges might be both devised and implemented at a lower political level or a particular organization. overbearing paternalism (Grüne-Yanoff 2012; Rebonato 2014; Rizzo and Whitman 2008;Whitman 2010;Whitman and Rizzo 2015). In the latter case, localized democratic control would be additional to the control already exercised at the central level.…”
Section: Democratic Controlmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The issue at hand is that soft paternalism interferes in a process that reaches into the individual's reflective preferences. Paternalist policies that are manipulative (and thus violate consumer sovereignty) will also interfere with reflective 16 On a general debate concerning the instability of preferences in the context of paternalist policies, see also Whitman and Rizzo (2015). A thorough discussion of preference learning is beyond the scope of this paper, but see e.g.…”
Section: V2 Reflective Preferences Are Tentative and Temporarymentioning
confidence: 99%