2017
DOI: 10.1111/phc3.12412
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The right and the wrong kind of reasons

Abstract: In a number of recent philosophical debates, it has become common to distinguish between two kinds of normative reasons, often called the right kind of reasons (henceforth: RKR) and the wrong kind of reasons (henceforth: WKR). The distinction was first introduced in discussions of the so-called buck-passing account of value, which aims to analyze value properties in terms of reasons for pro-attitudes and has been argued to face the wrong kind of reasons problem. But nowadays it also gets applied in other philo… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
27
0

Year Published

2018
2018
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
8
1

Relationship

0
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 56 publications
(29 citation statements)
references
References 43 publications
0
27
0
Order By: Relevance
“…This 'wrong for what? '-line of thought is compatible with the methodological shortcoming in the debate that this paper draws attention to.4 For overviews, seeGertken and Kiesewetter (2017) andSylvan (2016).5 Schroeder proposes a fourth earmark: 'pragmatic reasons for belief have a recognizable 'flavor' that makes them feel intuitively like reasons for other attitudes […]'. He himself thinks that this is 'arguably not a proper earmark in its own right' and does not spell it out further(Schroeder 2012: 460).6 This is connected to the debate about doxastic voluntarism, which I bracket.…”
mentioning
confidence: 70%
“…This 'wrong for what? '-line of thought is compatible with the methodological shortcoming in the debate that this paper draws attention to.4 For overviews, seeGertken and Kiesewetter (2017) andSylvan (2016).5 Schroeder proposes a fourth earmark: 'pragmatic reasons for belief have a recognizable 'flavor' that makes them feel intuitively like reasons for other attitudes […]'. He himself thinks that this is 'arguably not a proper earmark in its own right' and does not spell it out further(Schroeder 2012: 460).6 This is connected to the debate about doxastic voluntarism, which I bracket.…”
mentioning
confidence: 70%
“…In such cases, the moral reasons to make the promise have to do with avoiding serious harm to another and have nothing to do with the promise itself or the conventions governing permissible promise-making. This distinction is analogous to the distinction between the ‘right kind’ vs. ‘wrong kind’ of normative reasons—e.g., admiring Anne because she is admirable vs. admiring Diego because an evil demon threatened to destroy you if you did not do so (see Gertken and Kiesewetter [2017] for an overview of this literature).…”
Section: Framing the Questionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…I won't rehearse the back‐and‐forth here. However, as a recent discussion in this journal of the relevant literature reveals (Gertken & Kiesewetter, ), it's clear that, at least so far, no proposed solution to the WKR problem has gained wide acceptance . And I should highlight that, if it turns out there is no adequate solution to this problem to be had, then this would undermine not just a reasons‐based analysis of fittingness (and value), but also the currently fashionable approach to normativity in which this analysis figures, viz., the reasons‐first approach…”
Section: A Reasons‐based Accountmentioning
confidence: 99%