2023
DOI: 10.31234/osf.io/r5t2n
|View full text |Cite
Preprint
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Towards a Universal Theory of Consciousness

Ryota Kanai,
Ippei Fujisawa

Abstract: While falsifiability has been broadly discussed as a desirable property of a theory of consciousness, in this paper, we introduce the meta-theoretic concept of "Universality" as an additional desirable property for a theory of consciousness. The concept of universality, often assumed in physics, posits that the fundamental laws of nature are consistent and apply equally everywhere in the universe, and remain constant over time. This assumption is crucial in science, acting as a guiding principle for developing… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2

Citation Types

0
2
0

Year Published

2023
2023
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
2

Relationship

0
2

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 2 publications
(2 citation statements)
references
References 40 publications
0
2
0
Order By: Relevance
“…The second option is to adopt a more ambitious stance, by either formulating theories in a context-independent way [this is what Kanai and Fujisawa (2023) call ‘universality’] or by justifying extrapolations to the non-human case through arguments based on analogical reasoning, abductive reasoning, or a combination of both ( Melnyk, 1994 ). One could start, for example, from the structural similarities between the source domain (i.e., the domain for which the original hypothesis is formed, for example the domain of humans in the case of consciousness) and the target domain (i.e., the domain for which the hypothesis is supposed to hold, for example organisms radically different from humans and non-biological systems in the case of consciousness), and then claim that given that phenomenal properties correlate with specific properties in the source domain, the most parsimonious hypothesis is that a correlation between similar properties in the target and phenomenal properties occurs ( Barron and Klein, 2016 ; Godfrey-Smith, 2017 ; Bayne and Shea, 2020 ; Tsuchiya and Saigo, 2021 ; Birch, 2022 ).…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…The second option is to adopt a more ambitious stance, by either formulating theories in a context-independent way [this is what Kanai and Fujisawa (2023) call ‘universality’] or by justifying extrapolations to the non-human case through arguments based on analogical reasoning, abductive reasoning, or a combination of both ( Melnyk, 1994 ). One could start, for example, from the structural similarities between the source domain (i.e., the domain for which the original hypothesis is formed, for example the domain of humans in the case of consciousness) and the target domain (i.e., the domain for which the hypothesis is supposed to hold, for example organisms radically different from humans and non-biological systems in the case of consciousness), and then claim that given that phenomenal properties correlate with specific properties in the source domain, the most parsimonious hypothesis is that a correlation between similar properties in the target and phenomenal properties occurs ( Barron and Klein, 2016 ; Godfrey-Smith, 2017 ; Bayne and Shea, 2020 ; Tsuchiya and Saigo, 2021 ; Birch, 2022 ).…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…These two options have contrasting strengths and weaknesses: the humility principle can ensure that our applications of consciousness theories are more grounded, at the cost of limiting the explanatory power of such theories. Adopting the more ambitious stance, instead, can ensure stronger explanatory power, at the cost of either requiring a further ampliative argument or formulating theories that might end up being too liberal in their ascription of consciousness [for discussions, see ( Block, 1978 ; Block, 2002 ; Shevlin, 2021 ; Kanai and Fujisawa, 2023 )].…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%