Much of our knowledge is acquired not from direct experience but through the speech of others. Speech allows rapid and efficient transfer of information that is otherwise not directly observable. Do infants recognize that speech, even if unfamiliar, can communicate about an important aspect of the world that cannot be directly observed: a person's intentions? Twelve-month-olds saw a person (the Communicator) attempt but fail to achieve a target action (stacking a ring on a funnel). The Communicator subsequently directed either speech or a nonspeech vocalization to another person (the Recipient) who had not observed the attempts. The Recipient either successfully stacked the ring (Intended outcome), attempted but failed to stack the ring (Observable outcome), or performed a different stacking action (Related outcome). Infants recognized that speech could communicate about unobservable intentions, looking longer at Observable and Related outcomes than the Intended outcome when the Communicator used speech. However, when the Communicator used nonspeech, infants looked equally at the three outcomes. Thus, for 12-montholds, speech can transfer information about unobservable aspects of the world such as internal mental states, which provides preverbal infants with a tool for acquiring information beyond their immediate experience. (1-4). Adult humans use speech to transmit and acquire information about aspects of their environment that are directly observable (e.g., spilling coffee) but also about unobservable internal states such as beliefs, knowledge, and desires (e.g., wanting a refill). Speech is thus a powerful means of communication, which allows for rapid and efficient transfer of information that is otherwise not directly observable. Do preverbal infants recognize that speech can communicate information about another person's internal states? Such recognition would allow infants to use others' speech as a powerful mechanism for knowledge acquisition and provide a tool for acquiring information about what has not been or cannot be directly experienced (e.g., refs. 2, 5, and 6) even before they understand the meanings of particular words. Here, we examine whether 12-month-old infants understand that speech can communicate to a second person about an intention, an internal state that cannot be directly observed.By their first birthday, infants treat speech and nonspeech as functionally distinct when individuating and categorizing objects (7-9). For example, distinct speech labels (but not distinct tones or emotional vocalizations) leads infants to expect distinct objects (9), whereas pairing multiple individual category instances with the same speech label (but not tone) helps infants detect similarities between instances and generalize to novel instances (e.g., refs. 7 and 8). Further, when observing two people communicating with each other in a third-party interaction, 12-month-olds recognized that speech-but not nonspeech vocalizations-can communicate about a target object. That is, when a person (the