Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox 1979
DOI: 10.1007/978-94-015-7629-1_15
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Utility Theory: Axioms Versus ‘Paradoxes’

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

17
123
0
3

Year Published

2000
2000
2016
2016

Publication Types

Select...
5
4

Relationship

0
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 292 publications
(143 citation statements)
references
References 31 publications
17
123
0
3
Order By: Relevance
“…In a noncollapsed format, A, B, A' and B' in Table 1 can be presented as: A: 10% chance of $5m, 89% chance of $1m, and 1% chance of nothing B: $1m for certain A': 10% chance of $5m and 90% chance of nothing B': 11% chance of $1m and 89% chance of nothing Allais argued that when individuals are faced with choices between A & B and A' & B' in the non-collapsed format, many individuals will display a preference for B and A', which violates the independence axiom. Allais' proposition is known as the Allais paradox (or the common consequence effect), and has been empirically supported in subsequent analyses (Camerer, 1989;Conlisk, 1989;Kahneman & Tversky, 1979;MacCrimmon & Larsson, 1979;Morrison, 1967;Moskowitz, 1974;Slovic & Tversky, 1974). …”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 87%
“…In a noncollapsed format, A, B, A' and B' in Table 1 can be presented as: A: 10% chance of $5m, 89% chance of $1m, and 1% chance of nothing B: $1m for certain A': 10% chance of $5m and 90% chance of nothing B': 11% chance of $1m and 89% chance of nothing Allais argued that when individuals are faced with choices between A & B and A' & B' in the non-collapsed format, many individuals will display a preference for B and A', which violates the independence axiom. Allais' proposition is known as the Allais paradox (or the common consequence effect), and has been empirically supported in subsequent analyses (Camerer, 1989;Conlisk, 1989;Kahneman & Tversky, 1979;MacCrimmon & Larsson, 1979;Morrison, 1967;Moskowitz, 1974;Slovic & Tversky, 1974). …”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 87%
“…Allais 1953, MacCrimmon and Larsson 1979, Chew and Waller 1986, Wu 1994) that a significant majority of people exhibited a preference for A 1 in the first choice problem and a preference for B 2 in the second choice problem. Substituting EU immediately reveals that this leads to a conflicting relationship.…”
Section: Common Ratio Invariant Preferencesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In problem 3 the choice is between It has been observed in experiments that a significant majority of people exhibit a preference for A 3 in the former choice problem and a preference for B 4 in the latter choice problem (e.g. Allais 1953, MacCrimmon and Larsson 1979, Chew and Waller 1986, Wu 1994, but see also related evidence in Wakker, Erev and Weber 1994, Birnbaum and Navarette 1998, Birnbaum 2004 In the common consequence paradox the interpretation is that people are sensitive to replacing the good common consequence of getting "1 Million with probability 0.89" with a bad common consequence of getting "0 with probability 0.89." Therefore, also replacement separability (Machina 1989) is violated.…”
Section: Extreme Replacement Separabilitymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…8 If one views adherence to the compound lottery axiom as a requirement of rationality, then the results in Halevy (2007) show that ambiguity aversion is absent among those who are rational in this sense. 9 A probability-matching approach is also used in MacCrimmon and Larsson (1979), Kahn and Sarin (1988), and Viscusi and Magat (1992). Dimmock et al (2015) provide theoretical support for this method.…”
Section: Methodsmentioning
confidence: 99%