2016
DOI: 10.1016/j.cognition.2016.07.004
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Young children infer preferences from a single action, but not if it is constrained

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

4
58
0

Year Published

2018
2018
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
4
4
2

Relationship

1
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 35 publications
(62 citation statements)
references
References 45 publications
4
58
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Research suggests that inferences beyond goal attribution are supported by an expectation that agents make choices by quantifying, comparing, and maximizing subjective utilities-the difference between the costs they incur and the rewards they obtain. This Naïve Utility Calculus allows us to infer the knowledge, preferences, and moral values that explain other people's goals (Jara-Ettinger, Gweon, Schulz, & Tenenbaum, 2016;Jern, Lucas, & Kemp, 2017;Kleiman-Weiner, Saxe, & Tenenbaum, 2017;Lukas et al, 2014), and empirical work suggests that even young children share these expectations (Jara-Ettinger, Tenenbaum, & Schulz, 2015;Jara-Ettinger, Floyd, Tenenbaum, & Schulz, 2017;Pesowski, Denison, & Friedman, 2016;Lucas et al, 2014), with some basic form of the Naïve Utility Calculus in place in infancy (Liu, Ullman, Tenenbaum, & Spelke, 2017).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Research suggests that inferences beyond goal attribution are supported by an expectation that agents make choices by quantifying, comparing, and maximizing subjective utilities-the difference between the costs they incur and the rewards they obtain. This Naïve Utility Calculus allows us to infer the knowledge, preferences, and moral values that explain other people's goals (Jara-Ettinger, Gweon, Schulz, & Tenenbaum, 2016;Jern, Lucas, & Kemp, 2017;Kleiman-Weiner, Saxe, & Tenenbaum, 2017;Lukas et al, 2014), and empirical work suggests that even young children share these expectations (Jara-Ettinger, Tenenbaum, & Schulz, 2015;Jara-Ettinger, Floyd, Tenenbaum, & Schulz, 2017;Pesowski, Denison, & Friedman, 2016;Lucas et al, 2014), with some basic form of the Naïve Utility Calculus in place in infancy (Liu, Ullman, Tenenbaum, & Spelke, 2017).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…However, there are reasons to believe that the prerequisite inferential and evaluative capacities for such understanding are present in early childhood. First, even infants can infer others' intentions and preferences from their choices (Repacholi & Gopnik, 1997;Phillips & Wellman, 2005;Woodward, 2009); some studies suggest that these inferences are made in light of alternative actions that are available to the actor in the context (Gergely, Bekkering, & Kiraly, 2002;Kushnir, Xu, & Wellman, 2010;Kushnir, 2018;Pesowski, Denison, & Friedman, 2016). Toddlers and preschoolers are more likely to interpret an agent's choice as an indicator of her underlying preferences when the agent foregoes more probable alternative options and chooses a less probable option instead (Kushnir et al, 2010; see EVALUATIONS OF SOCIAL MINDFULNESS 7 also Gweon, Tenenbaum, & Schulz, 2010 for a similar sensitivity, but about inferring object properties).…”
Section: Evaluations Of Social Mindfulnessmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Even young children's intuitions about other people's preferences align with the predictions of the Naïve Utility Calculus. Five-year-olds infer high rewards when an agent incurs a high cost and, conversely, they infer high costs when an agent foregoes a high reward (Jara-Ettinger, Gweon, Tenenbaum, & Schulz, 2015;Pesowski, Denison, & Friedman, 2016). Children at this age also understand that agents do not maximize the utilities they obtain, but the utilities they expect to obtain.…”
Section: The Naïve Utility Calculusmentioning
confidence: 99%