1978
DOI: 10.1037/0096-1523.4.3.497
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

An experimental study of risk preference in lotteries.

Abstract: to y ield a nsk order ' and thus a behaviorally tional Institutes of Health Training Grant GM-derived risk order would be obtained. Risk-01231-13. This paper has benefited from discussions taking behavior and many questions of theowith David Krantz.retical interest pertaining to the nature of Requests for reprints should be sent to Clyde H. 1 1 -1 -1 i j j Coombs, 580 Union Drive, Ann Arbor, Michigan psychological risk are then opened to study 48109.in a well-controlled way.

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

1
9
0

Year Published

1980
1980
2004
2004

Publication Types

Select...
6
1

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 12 publications
(10 citation statements)
references
References 14 publications
1
9
0
Order By: Relevance
“…The greater inconsistency of data generated by pick l/p methods relative to reject I/p methods reported by Coombs et al (1978) was replicated in this study. However, this was only true under certain circumstances.…”
Section: Discussionsupporting
confidence: 68%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…The greater inconsistency of data generated by pick l/p methods relative to reject I/p methods reported by Coombs et al (1978) was replicated in this study. However, this was only true under certain circumstances.…”
Section: Discussionsupporting
confidence: 68%
“…Once the preference orderings were constructed, the number of inconsistencies were determined. One approach is to divide in half the sum of the absolute differences between the expected frequencies obtained from the Method of Expected Matrices (Coombs, 1964) and the resultant frequencies derived from the data (e.g., Coombs et al, 1978). This method, however, only establishes a lower bound for the number of inconsistencies.…”
Section: Determination Of the Number Of Inconsistenciesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The situation parallels several which have appeared in the literature. One example is that of models of choice which incorporate "risk" as a construct, in the absence of a well-characterized concept of risk (e.g., Coombs, Donnell, & Kirk, 1978;Coombs & Huang, 1970;Libby & Fishburn, 1977;Slavic, 1964). The approach is to extract some property, or properties, of the undefined concept about which there is consensus.…”
Section: Differentiating the Modelsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…When presented with a larger set of alternatives, we are generally expected to exhibit a similar preference ranking regardless of whether we choose the alternatives starting with the best and ending at the worst, or reject them starting at the worst and ending with the best. Coombs, Donnell, and Kirk (1978), for example, document similar rankings of three lotteries obtained by choice and by rejection. The lotteries used by these investigators, however, were unlikely to yield the kind of compatibility effects documented above.…”
Section: Nonbinary Problemsmentioning
confidence: 99%