2012
DOI: 10.1037/a0027372
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Behavioral variability of choices versus structural inconsistency of preferences.

Abstract: Theories of rational choice often make the structural consistency assumption that every decision maker’s binary strict preference among choice alternatives forms a strict weak order. Likewise, the very concept of a utility function over lotteries in normative, prescriptive, and descriptive theory is mathematically equivalent to strict weak order preferences over those lotteries, while intransitive heuristic models violate such weak orders. Using new quantitative interdisciplinary methodologies we dissociate va… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

1
85
1

Year Published

2015
2015
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
7
2

Relationship

3
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 71 publications
(87 citation statements)
references
References 30 publications
1
85
1
Order By: Relevance
“…First, in line with previous results, the vast majority of participants (90 percent) choose different lotteries in the three repetitions of the same question of subjects gave different answers to the same question. Many studies have replicated this result, focusing on choices between risky gambles: Camerer (1989a), Starmer and Sugden (1989), Hey and Orme (1994), Ballinger and Wilcox (1997), Hey (2001), Regenwetter, Dana, and Davis-Stober (2011), and Regenwetter and Davis-Stober (2012). tion when these repetitions are distant from each other.…”
mentioning
confidence: 73%
“…First, in line with previous results, the vast majority of participants (90 percent) choose different lotteries in the three repetitions of the same question of subjects gave different answers to the same question. Many studies have replicated this result, focusing on choices between risky gambles: Camerer (1989a), Starmer and Sugden (1989), Hey and Orme (1994), Ballinger and Wilcox (1997), Hey (2001), Regenwetter, Dana, and Davis-Stober (2011), and Regenwetter and Davis-Stober (2012). tion when these repetitions are distant from each other.…”
mentioning
confidence: 73%
“…Due to the mathematical complexity of higher-order choice structures, studies have used a binary forced choice framework that does not explicitly include indifference, even though indifference is a defining aspect of the lexicographic semiorder structure (see Regenwetter & Davis-Stober, 2012, for an indepth discussion of this limitation). 2.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The cells record, respectively, the total number of FDI's, and the number of their equivalence classes under relabellings of the elements in [n]. The values come from - Fiorini (2001) for the partial order polytope P n PO ; -Regenwetter & Davis-Stober (2012a) for the interval order polytope P n IO and for the semiorder polytope P n SO ; -Fiorini (2001), Fiorini & Fishburn (2004) and Regenwetter & Davis-Stober (2012b) for the (strict) weak order polytope P n SWO ;…”
Section: The Difficulties In Finding All Fdi'smentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The strict weak order polytope P n SWO (Regenwetter & Davis-Stober, 2012b) is closely linked to still another polytope, the weak order polytope P n WO (studied in Doignon & Fiorini, 2002;Fiorini & Fishburn, 2004;Regenwetter & Davis-Stober, 2008). A weak order (or complete preorder) on [n] is a relation which is reflexive, transitive and total.…”
Section: Searching For the Primary Facet-definingmentioning
confidence: 99%