2013
DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199669424.001.0001
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Berkeley's Argument for Idealism

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
9
0
1

Year Published

2015
2015
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
5
2
1

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 25 publications
(10 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
0
9
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…Ott and Holden both argue that Berkeley explicitly rejects this principle (citing, e.g., PHK §81 and DHP 232-33). See Pappas 1995, Rickless 2013: 112, 132, 181-82, Winkler 1989: 30-31, Ott 2015, Holden 2019 located. These are extrinsic properties of the post box.…”
Section: The Intrinsic Properties Of Ideas As Transparentmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Ott and Holden both argue that Berkeley explicitly rejects this principle (citing, e.g., PHK §81 and DHP 232-33). See Pappas 1995, Rickless 2013: 112, 132, 181-82, Winkler 1989: 30-31, Ott 2015, Holden 2019 located. These are extrinsic properties of the post box.…”
Section: The Intrinsic Properties Of Ideas As Transparentmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…11 Samuel Rickless has recently argued forcefully for a version of this interpretation. For a summary of Rickless' interpretation and the role the inseparability argument plays for Berkeley, see Rickless 2013, 185-187. Lisa Downing (2018 argues that the inseparability argument blocks a path that Berkeley's non-idealist interlocutors could have used to escape his attacks, if Berkeley only had the perceptual relativity arguments and his arguments from the immediacy of perceived things at his disposal.…”
Section: Incomplete Argumentsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“… For instance, Winkler (/2001, 30‐31) writes that “[o]ne of Berkeley's most deeply held beliefs is that conceivability and possibility coincide”: that “a state of affairs is conceivable […] if and only if it is possible.” Rickless (, 112, 132, 181‐2) and Grayling (, 173) also each state categorically that Berkeley accepts the inconceivability principle, while Kail (, 275) asserts that, for Berkeley, “something's being inconceivable is determined by its involving a contradiction”—in which case inconceivability would entail contradictoriness, and hence, presumably, impossibility. Somewhat more hedged, Pappas (, 133) writes that “Berkeley seems to have accepted” the inconceivability principle; Stoneham (, 135) asserts that Berkeley “probably” held that inconceivability entails impossibility; and Dancy (, 31) similarly finds it “probable” that Berkeley “saw no difference between the question what is possible and the question what is conceivable.” The only commentator I am aware of on the other side of this issue is Ott (, 411), who touches on the question only in passing. …”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“… Rickless (, 181‐7) argues that Berkeley's overall case for idealism rests on his argument that primary qualities are inseparable from secondary qualities (‘the inseparability argument,’ as I call it—see below), which argument Rickless interprets as requiring the inconceivability principle. …”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation