2011
DOI: 10.1007/s12646-011-0079-9
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Can Jurors Free Themselves from Retributive Objectives?

Abstract: We examined the hypothesis that the conscious self-correction process in the models of lay citizens' determination of punishment could inhibit the retributive goal that was their instinctive default objective. In two experiments, we tested whether an instruction to ignore the retributive goal could eliminate the influence of information about the seriousness of the crime on the severity of the punishment. If the retributive goal can be inhibited, the instruction would eliminate the information's influence on t… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
3
1

Citation Types

0
5
0

Year Published

2014
2014
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
5

Relationship

4
1

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 5 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 15 publications
0
5
0
Order By: Relevance
“…By combining two theoretical frameworks, namely, the framing effect (e.g., Gong et al, 2013; Kühberger, 1998; Levin et al, 1985; Tversky & Kahneman, 1981) and retributive justification (Brubacher, 2018; Carlsmith, 2006; Keller et al, 2010; Rucker et al, 2004; Watamura et al, 2011), this study examined the effects of experimentally manipulating the loss caused by false accusations on attitudes toward the death penalty. We found no difference in support for the death penalty between groups with or without information that emphasized the unique loss from retribution justification, given that the number of true criminals evading justice is the same as the number of people falsely convicted.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…By combining two theoretical frameworks, namely, the framing effect (e.g., Gong et al, 2013; Kühberger, 1998; Levin et al, 1985; Tversky & Kahneman, 1981) and retributive justification (Brubacher, 2018; Carlsmith, 2006; Keller et al, 2010; Rucker et al, 2004; Watamura et al, 2011), this study examined the effects of experimentally manipulating the loss caused by false accusations on attitudes toward the death penalty. We found no difference in support for the death penalty between groups with or without information that emphasized the unique loss from retribution justification, given that the number of true criminals evading justice is the same as the number of people falsely convicted.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The cognitive-psychology literature has robustly confirmed that humans tend to make loss-averse judgments and are less likely to accept alternatives that emphasize losses (i.e., the framing effect; Chong & Druckman, 2007; Gong et al, 2013; Kühberger, 1998; Levin et al, 1985; Tversky & Kahneman, 1981). The public’s attitude regarding the punishment of offenders is based on retributive justification, which seeks to offset crime through punishment (Brubacher, 2018; Carlsmith, 2006; Carlsmith & Darley, 2008; Finckenauer, 1988; Keller et al, 2010; Rucker et al, 2004; Watamura et al, 2011). The public must therefore view the “other side of the coin” of a wrongful conviction, that is, the real culprit going unpunished, as a loss.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…These studies have suggested that laypeople prefer retributive focused philosophies, as opposed to the human image of living in a civilized society that is receptive to the mistakes of the accused. Laypeople tend to resolve moral imbalances by harsh punishment commensurate with the severity of the crime, without much consideration of the practical effects of the punishment [ 1 4 , 7 13 ]. Prior studies have found positive arguments supporting the fact that retribution serves as the perpetrator’s compensation to society [ 14 ] and that it should not be neglected to maintain public confidence in the judiciary [ 15 ].…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Previous empirical studies have reported that the public adopts retribution as the predominant or nearly sole justification (McCorkle, 1993;Weiner et al, 1997;Carlsmith et al, 2002;Oswald et al, 2002;Orth, 2003;Rucker et al, 2004;Carlsmith, 2006Carlsmith, , 2008Alter et al, 2007;Carlsmith and Darley, 2008;Gromet and Darley, 2009;Okimoto et al, 2009;Keller et al, 2010;Watamura et al, 2011;Gerber and Jackson, 2013;Twardawski et al, 2020). With respect to sentencing decisions for serious crimes such as murder, retribution is the default justification ".…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%