2019
DOI: 10.3982/ecta14156
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Coalitional Expected Multi‐Utility Theory

Abstract: This paper begins by observing that any reflexive binary (preference) relation (over risky prospects) that satisfies the independence axiom admits a form of expected utility representation. We refer to this representation notion as the coalitional minmax expected utility representation. By adding the remaining properties of the expected utility theorem, namely, continuity, completeness, and transitivity, one by one, we find how this representation gets sharper and sharper, thereby deducing the versions of this… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
24
0

Year Published

2019
2019
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
8

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 25 publications
(24 citation statements)
references
References 51 publications
0
24
0
Order By: Relevance
“… See Aumann (1962, Footnote 25). We invite the reader to use Propositions 1, 2 and Footnote 5 above to see the relationship between the continuity assumptions of this paper and those inAumann (1962, (4.1) and (4.2)).22 See Karni (2014) for a recent survey andHara et al (2015) for the state-of-the-art results in this line of literature.…”
mentioning
confidence: 91%
“… See Aumann (1962, Footnote 25). We invite the reader to use Propositions 1, 2 and Footnote 5 above to see the relationship between the continuity assumptions of this paper and those inAumann (1962, (4.1) and (4.2)).22 See Karni (2014) for a recent survey andHara et al (2015) for the state-of-the-art results in this line of literature.…”
mentioning
confidence: 91%
“…Nevertheless, standard arguments imply that the utility u under BEU is unique up to positive affine transformation. Moreover, Supplementary Appendix S.1 shows that the belief-set collection P is unique up to "half-space closure," analogous to recent representations featuring collections of sets of utilities (e.g., Hara, Ok, and Riella, 2019).…”
Section: Relevant Priorsmentioning
confidence: 89%
“…Related to the structure of DSEU, several recent papers employ belief-set or utility-set collections in other contexts. While we maintain the weak order axiom and focus on relaxing independence, Lehrer and Teper (2011), Nascimento and Riella (2011), Nishimura and Ok (2016), Hara, Ok, and Riella (2019), and Aguiar, Hjertstrand, and Serrano (2020) study preferences that violate completeness and/or transitivity. 6 Whereas DSEU is a utility representation, these papers provide generalized unanimity representations à la Bewley (2002) and Dubra, Maccheroni, and Ok (2004), and the resulting proof methods are quite different.…”
Section: Related Literaturementioning
confidence: 99%
“…The uniqueness of P up to half-space closure parallels the identification result in Hara, Ok, and Riella (2019), who represent independent (but possibly incomplete and intransitive) preferences over lotteries using a collection of utility-sets. Analogous to Hara, Ok, and Riella (2019), the idea is that for any P ∈ P, the closed half-spaces containing P capture all information about P that is relevant to the representation. Indeed, in determining how any given utility act φ ∈ R S is evaluated by the representation, the only relevant feature of P is the worst-case expectation λ P,φ := min µ∈P E µ [φ], and this worst-case expectation is shared by the closed half-space H φ,λ P,φ ⊇ P .…”
Section: Uniquenessmentioning
confidence: 99%