2017
DOI: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.00221
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Cognitive Penetration and Attention

Abstract: Zenon Pylyshyn argues that cognitively driven attentional effects do not amount to cognitive penetration of early vision because such effects occur either before or after early vision. Critics object that in fact such effects occur at all levels of perceptual processing. We argue that Pylyshyn’s claim is correct—but not for the reason he emphasizes. Even if his critics are correct that attentional effects are not external to early vision, these effects do not satisfy Pylyshyn’s requirements that the effects be… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
22
0

Year Published

2017
2017
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
3
3
2
1

Relationship

0
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 30 publications
(22 citation statements)
references
References 73 publications
0
22
0
Order By: Relevance
“…A related idea has been defended by Zenon Pylyshyn, who first coined the term ‘cognitive penetration.’ Pylyshyn argues that cognitive penetration requires that beliefs have a “semantically coherent” (1999: 343) influence upon perception on the basis that causal influence is insufficient. While this idea has not gone unchallenged (Stokes ), it has been robustly defended by Fiona Macpherson (: 26; Macpherson : 9–10), and is often claimed to be partially definitive of the phenomenon (Brogaard and Gatzia ; Burnston ; Fridland ; Gross ; Lupyan ; Teng ; Wu ). In particular, Macpherson argues that the semantic coherence condition can help distinguish cases of cognitive penetration from cases like the following:…”
Section: Cognitive Penetration and Representational Contentmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…A related idea has been defended by Zenon Pylyshyn, who first coined the term ‘cognitive penetration.’ Pylyshyn argues that cognitive penetration requires that beliefs have a “semantically coherent” (1999: 343) influence upon perception on the basis that causal influence is insufficient. While this idea has not gone unchallenged (Stokes ), it has been robustly defended by Fiona Macpherson (: 26; Macpherson : 9–10), and is often claimed to be partially definitive of the phenomenon (Brogaard and Gatzia ; Burnston ; Fridland ; Gross ; Lupyan ; Teng ; Wu ). In particular, Macpherson argues that the semantic coherence condition can help distinguish cases of cognitive penetration from cases like the following:…”
Section: Cognitive Penetration and Representational Contentmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The processes that underlie integration and segregation are affected not only by these stimulus features but also by internal states of the listener, such as the degree to which they are attending to the sounds (Carlyon et al, 2001;Sussman et al, 2002;Snyder et al, 2006;Billig and Carlyon, 2015), and by whether the stimuli correspond to a familiar speaker (Johnsrude et al, 2013) or word (Billig et al, 2013). The extent to which observers can voluntarily influence how they perceptually organize the outside world is unclear and bears on questions of whether and how higher-level cognition can influence perception (Fodor, 1983;Pylyshyn, 1999;Firestone and Scholl, 2015;Gross, 2017;Lupyan, 2017).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For some alternative approaches to setting up the issues, see Stokes (2012), Shea (2015), or Gross (2017). …”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For an example of this point in the literature, see Firestone and Scholl (2016). For critical discussion of the point and of how strong a conclusion can be drawn from it, see Lupyan (2015), Gross (2017) or Green (forthcoming).…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%