2001
DOI: 10.1017/cbo9780511492303
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Domain Conditions in Social Choice Theory

Abstract: Preface and acknowledgements xi 1 Introduction 2 Notation, definitions, and two fundamental theorems 3 The existence of collective choice rules under exclusion conditions for finite sets of discrete alternatives 3.1 The method of majority decision 3.1.1 The case where the individual preferences are orderings 3.1.1.1 The method of majority decision is a social welfare function 3.1.1.2 The method of majority decision is a social decision function 3.1.1.3 The method of majority decision and order restricted prefe… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
54
0

Year Published

2009
2009
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
5
3

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 80 publications
(54 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
0
54
0
Order By: Relevance
“…In still a different framework, Nehring (2003) derives a version of Arrow's theorem for weak preferences that involves a monotonic addition to independence of irrelevant alternatives. 35 Such as those described by Gaertner (2006) and Le Breton and Weymark (2011). In classical propositional logic, there are at least two agendas that could give rise to this, i.e. X = {a, a ∨ b} ± and X = {a ∧ b, a → b} ± , and it would be a conceptual abuse to treat them as they were the same.…”
Section: And Non-dictatorship Being Replaced By Non-oligarchymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In still a different framework, Nehring (2003) derives a version of Arrow's theorem for weak preferences that involves a monotonic addition to independence of irrelevant alternatives. 35 Such as those described by Gaertner (2006) and Le Breton and Weymark (2011). In classical propositional logic, there are at least two agendas that could give rise to this, i.e. X = {a, a ∨ b} ± and X = {a ∧ b, a → b} ± , and it would be a conceptual abuse to treat them as they were the same.…”
Section: And Non-dictatorship Being Replaced By Non-oligarchymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In the case of unidimensional alignment, the extreme positions on the given dimension correspond to either clear acceptance or clear rejection of each proposition, and, for each proposition, there is a threshold between these extremes (which may vary across propositions) that divides the 'acceptance-region'from the 'rejection-region'. 16 On unidimensionally ordered pro…les, majority voting preserves consistency, and we can say something about the nature of its outcome: it is a subset of the middle individual's judgment set (or, for even n, a subset of the intersection of the two middle individuals' judgment sets). If the pro…le is unidimensionally aligned, the majority outcome is not just included in that set but coincides with it.…”
Section: Conditions Based On Orders Of Individualsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The following result answers this question. 17 Proposition 7 (a) Restricted to pro…les of consistent judgment sets, 16 In List [21], unidimensional alignment is interpreted in terms of 'meta-agreement'. 17 The non-implication claims in (a) do not refer to a …xed agenda X and group size n. Rather, for some (in fact, most) X and n, there are pro…les satisfying one condition but not the other.…”
Section: The Logical Relationships Between the Four Conditionsmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…First it allows one to provide some endogenous domain restrictions on the space of admissible preferences or on the set of utilities functions considered in aggregation procedures. Restrictions of domains have been thought as one way to escape the gloom of Arrow's or Sen's [64] theorems and have been at the origin of a large literature whose a thorough account can be found in Gaertner [36]. For instance, it is often assumed that the individual utility function are concave.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%