2015
DOI: 10.1080/00455091.2015.1123454
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Don’t stop believing

Abstract: It’s been argued that there are no diachronic norms of epistemic rationality. These arguments come partly in response to certain kinds of counterexamples to Conditionalization, but are mainly motivated by a form of internalism that appears to be in tension with any sort of diachronic coherence requirements. I argue that there are, in fact, fundamentally diachronic norms of rationality. And this is to reject at least a strong version of internalism. But I suggest a replacement for Conditionalization that salvag… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
11
0

Year Published

2015
2015
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
8

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 14 publications
(11 citation statements)
references
References 17 publications
0
11
0
Order By: Relevance
“…(See, for example, [Seidenfeld, 1994], [Stalnaker, 1999]). Recently, several philosophers have addressed this question directly; see, for example: [Carr, 2015], [Ferrero, 2012[Ferrero, , 2008, [Hedden, 2015b,a], [Meacham, 2010b], [Moss, 2013].…”
Section: Time-slice Rationalitymentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…(See, for example, [Seidenfeld, 1994], [Stalnaker, 1999]). Recently, several philosophers have addressed this question directly; see, for example: [Carr, 2015], [Ferrero, 2012[Ferrero, , 2008, [Hedden, 2015b,a], [Meacham, 2010b], [Moss, 2013].…”
Section: Time-slice Rationalitymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…4 See [Hedden, 2015a], [Moss, 2013], and [Carr, 2015] for more discussion on the motivation internalism provides for Time-Slice Rationality. I think the most helpful way to see the point is to focus on the so-called "action-guiding" role of the rational 'ought.'…”
Section: Time-slice Rationalitymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Paul goes on to suggest that, because temptation pre-2 I am presuming in this discussion that diachronic norms of rationality govern our resolutions, such that something goes wrong with you if you abandon your resolution without good reason. There is currently a live philosophical debate about whether irreducibly diachronic norms of (epistemic and/or practical) rationality exist (for example, see Christensen 2000, Ferrero 2012, Hedden 2015and Moss 2015 for arguments that no such norms exist, and Bratman 1987, Holton 2009, Broome 2013, Hlobil 2015and Carr 2016 for arguments that they do). However, I do not need to delve into this debate for present purposes, since one could translate Holton's (and my) claims about the stability of resolutions into a "timeslice rationality" framework that denies the existence of irreducible diachronic norms of practical rationality.…”
Section: The Efficacy Objectionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…But both Moss and Meacham are motivated by different kinds of considerations than Hedden. For a defense of diachronic credence constraints, see Carr (2016). is a subject's initial credence function, (ii) an ur-prior function can be any function which bears the right relations to a subject's credences and evidence over time, and (iii) the ur-prior function is a function representing the subject's evidential standards.…”
Section: Ur-prior Conditionalizationmentioning
confidence: 99%